Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 15 November 2011
Sec. Cognition
This article is part of the Research Topic Human preferences and risky choices View all 21 articles

The Stability of Preferences – A Social-Cognition View

  • Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Erfurt, Germany

Attitudes guide behavior. The social-cognitive approach to decision-making has been building on this assumption for almost a century (Allport, 1935). In this field, the model of reasoned action (Fishbein and Ajzen, 1974) was probably the most influential advance in describing the relation between attitudes and behavior. Accordingly, attitudes are the key predictor of behavioral intentions. They are formally described as a function of a linear integration of evaluations and probabilities (beliefs). The attitudinal part of the model dovetails with the subjectively expected-utility (SEU) approach to risky decision-making (Edwards, 1954). In line with attitude–behavior models, preferences are stable attitudes toward behaviors.

After its formation, an attitude can be stored in memory in association with the attitude object (e.g., Fazio, 1990; Wilson et al., 2000; Betsch, 2005). Attitude storage opens the path to stability. If a person re-encounters an attitude object, she can look up her attitude in memory and use it for subsequent judgment and choice. Individual preferences should be stable to the extent that the person relies on stored attitudes.

This so-called “file-drawer” notion (Wilson and Hodges, 1992), however, has been challenged by empirical evidence. Attitudinal responses in risky and non-risky choice domains were shown to be susceptible to a variety of task conditions. Krosnick and Schuman (1988) showed that response order, question wording and format systematically affect attitude judgments irrespective of their subjective importance, extremity, and certainty. In a similar vein, empirical violations of the axioms of decision theory challenged the notion that preferences are stable (e.g., framing effect, Tversky and Kahneman, 1981).

The temporary construal approach, in its extreme version, assumes that individuals always construct attitudes on the spot (Schwarz, 2000). In this view, stability is a function of the situation. In stable situations the sample of information (salient stimuli, activated knowledge) is invariant. Consequently, attitudinal judgments and behaviors are expected to be stable. If the situation changes, however, the sample of information changes as well and so will attitudes and behaviors. Accordingly, attitudes are transient constructions. Therefore, preferences cannot be stable.

The focus on variability, however, is prone to yield an un-representative picture of human behavior. Numerous examples of behavioral rigidity can be cited, both from everyday observation and controlled studies. Individuals regularly obey norms, repeat their routines, and fancy the same things two days in a row. Correspondingly, there is a bulk of psychological research demonstrating stability, especially in the field of learning. In their famous demonstrations of the Einstellung-Effect, Luchins and Luchins (1959) showed that only a few implementations of a problem-solving strategy suffice to induce a tendency to maintain the strategy even when less costly strategies are adequate. In recurrent risky choices, prior experience fosters maintenance of behavioral options (Betsch et al., 2001) and decision strategies (Bröder and Schiffer, 2006), even following changes in the pay-off structure that render the routine a maladaptive choice. A few behavior repetitions (less than 10) suffice to induce counter-intentional relapse errors1 in subsequent choice (Betsch et al., 2004). In research on attitude–behavior models, Bentler and Speckart (1979), for instance, suggested including past behavior as an additional predictor in the Fishbein–Ajzen model.

How is it possible that there is evidence for both variability and stability in behavior? Many studies on variability employ tasks and judgment domains in which individuals lack behavioral experience. In contrast, studies on stability often assess behavior in recurrent tasks. It is widely acknowledged, however, that experience matters. Decisions based on experience yield different results from those in one-shot situations (e.g., Hertwig et al., 2004). Thus, one might conclude that preferences should be labile in new situations and stabilize with behavioral experience.

Note, however, that the behavioral invariance observed in recurrent and experienced-based situations is not a sufficient condition for inferring preference stability. According to attitude theory, preferential stability requires that the attitude remains stable and guides choice. Repetitive experience, however, could merely result in increasing the association between a stimulus and a response. If this were the case, we would expect stability in recurrent situations and variability when situations change in the sense that the learned stimulus is no longer present. Explaining stability in stable situations does not necessitate the assumption of a stable attitude because it is the stimulus situation and not the attitude that might induce stable responses. Stimulus-directed choice is likely to occur if a behavior has been repeated so frequently in the past that it has been “frozen into habit” (James, 1890/1950; Verplanken and Aarts, 1999). Habits are responses that are instantiated automatically upon recognizing the associated stimulus. Indeed, there is evidence that highly frequent behavior repetition can outperform attitudes and intentions (Ouellette and Wood, 1998). On the other hand, the fact that habits are implemented in a stimulus-directed fashion without involving goals and intentions (Wood and Neal, 2007) does not speak against the possibility that attitudes can also become stable with behavior repetition and may systematically guide intentional decisions.

Two conditions must be met to justify the assumption that repetition paves the way to preference stability. First, previous behavior must increase the association between an attitude and an object. Accordingly, response latencies for attitude judgments were found to decrease with increasing frequency of prior activation of the attitude object (Fazio et al., 1986). Most important, studies using a conceptual priming technique show that activation of an attitude object can result in automatic activation of attitudes (Fazio et al., 1986).

Second, if it is truly the attitude that can guide behavior in intentional decisions, than we should observe a generalization of the preferred behavior to conditions that deviate from those under which the behavior has been learned. Generalization should occur especially for frequent compared to infrequent behaviors because in the former the behavior–attitude association is strong. Such transfer effects could not easily be accounted for by a stimulus–response model.

The following demonstration provides evidence of a generalization of strong attitudes. Sixty undergraduates from various majors at the University of Erfurt received vignettes involving food choices in everyday settings. Half of the behaviors were frequently performed in the past, such as drinking coffee or tea at breakfast. Others were infrequent such as foreign meals offered on the exchange-students day. Measures of attitudes toward the alternatives (nine-point rating scale: dislike–like) and choices were assessed twice with a 2-week delay in between. At the second assessment, participants were randomly assigned to two conditions. Half of the participants received descriptions of new situations mostly atypical of everyday settings. The other half received the same descriptions that they were exposed to at the first assessment. Even though the situations differed between the two conditions, the set of alternatives was identical.

Mean correlations (r) between attitudes and choices over vignettes were generally above 0.50 and significant – both within and between the two times of measurement. First-time attitudes and choices were equally strongly associated with second-time choices. These results indicate that attitude–choice relations were quite strong and stable over time. More revealing, however, are the results from a comparison of old and new situations. For frequent behaviors, the correlations between the first-time attitudes and choices and second-time choices were substantially larger in new (mean r = 0.90) as compared to old situations (mean r = 0.66). For infrequent behaviors, a reverse pattern for old (r = 0.70) and new situations (r = 0.59) was obtained.

Not only the predictive power of past choices but also the predictive power of attitudes seems to stabilize with behavior repetition over time and situations. Generalization indicates that behavior repetition appears to stabilize preferences beyond creating mere stimulus–response associations. Hence, one might conclude that stability in preferences is a function of behavioral repetition and storage processes.

Attitude research, however, suggests that consolidation of attitude–behavior relations in memory is not a sufficient condition for stability because the cognitive processes at the time of decision matter as well. Individuals can use different styles of thinking involving more or less deliberative effort (Evans, 2008). Economists often assume that individuals must think carefully to arrive at good (rational) decisions (Hertwig and Ortmann, 2001, for a discussion). Thus, violations of the axioms of rationality (e.g., preference reversals) may be attributed to shallow thinking under flawed incentive structures.

Does thorough thinking foster stability? When considering theorizing and empirical results from attitude research, one arrives at the opposite prediction. In his MODE-model, Fazio (1990) assumes that reliance on stored attitudes increases the less a person is motivated and able to think carefully about the decision. Under high motivation and in the absence of constraints, the individual is expected to engage in a new assessment of risks and benefits. In line with this prediction, individuals have been found to change preferences when “thinking too much” (Wilson and Schooler, 1991). Accordingly, individuals should be more likely to rely on prior attitudes if they make decisions without investing much cognitive effort (Betsch and Glöckner, 2010).

From the social-cognition approach, we can conclude that preferences (attitudes) can indeed stabilize and yield stability in judgment and decision-making under certain conditions. Stability is probably a joint function of memory and judgment processes. We should expect stability to increase with behavior repetition in the past and when individuals do not think much before making their decisions.

Footnote

  1. ^ A relapse error occurs if the actor performs a routine behavior against his or her intention to deviate from this routine.

References

Allport, G. W. (1935). “Attitudes“ in Handbook of Social Psychology, ed. C. Murchison (Worcester, MA: Clark University Press), 798–844.

Bentler, P. M., and Speckart, G. (1979). Models of attitude-behavior relations. Psychol. Rev. 86, 452–464.

CrossRef Full Text

Betsch, T. (2005). “Preference theory – an affect-based approach to recurrent decision making” in The Routines of Decision Making, eds T. Betsch, and S. Haberstroh (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum), 39–65.

Betsch, T., and Glöckner, A. (2010). Intuition in judgment and decision making: extensive thinking without effort. Psychol. Inq. 21, 1–16.

CrossRef Full Text

Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., Glöckner, A., Haar, T., and Fiedler, K. (2001). The effects of routine strength on information acquisition and adaptation in recurrent decision making. Organ. Behav. Hum. Dec. 84, 23–53.

CrossRef Full Text

Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., Molter, B., and Glöckner, A. (2004). Oops, I did it again – relapse errors in routinized decision making. Organ. Behav. Hum. Dec. 93, 62–74.

CrossRef Full Text

Bröder, A., and Schiffer, S. (2006). Adaptive flexibility and maladaptive routines in selecting fast and frugal decision strategies. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 32, 904–918.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Edwards, W. (1954). The theory of decision making. Psychol. Bull. 51, 380–417.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 255–278.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Fazio, R. H. (1990). Multiple processes by which attitudes guide behavior: the MODE model as an integrative framework. Adv. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 23, 75–109.

CrossRef Full Text

Fazio, R. H., Sanbonmatsu, D. M., Powell, M. C., and Kardes, F. R. (1986). On the automatic activation of attitudes. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 50, 229–238.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Fishbein, M., and Ajzen, I. (1974). Attitudes towards objects as predictors of single and multiple behavioral criteria. Psychol. Rev. 81, 59–74.

CrossRef Full Text

Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E. U., and Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effects of rare events in risky choice. Psychol. Sci. 15, 534–539.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hertwig, R., and Ortmann, A. (2001). Experimental practices in economics: a methodological challenge for psychologists. Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 383–451.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

James, W. (1890/1950). The Principles of Psychology, Vol. 1. New York: Dover.

Krosnick, J. A., and Schuman, H. (1988). Attitude intensity, importance, and certainty and susceptibility to response effects. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 54, 940–952.

CrossRef Full Text

Luchins, A. S., and Luchins, E. H. (1959). Rigidity of Behavior. A Variational Approach to the Effect of Einstellung. Eugene: University of Oregon Press.

Ouellette, J. A., and Wood, W. (1998). Habit and intention in everyday life: the multiple processes by which past behavior predicts future behavior. Psychol. Bull. 124, 54–74.

CrossRef Full Text

Schwarz, N. (2000). AGENDA 2000 – Social judgment and attitudes: warmer, more social, and less conscious. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. 30, 149–176.

CrossRef Full Text

Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211, 453–458.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Verplanken, B., and Aarts, H. (1999). Habit, attitude, and planned behavior: is habit an empty construct or an interesting case of goal-directed automaticity? Eur. Rev. Soc. Psychol. 10, 101–134.

CrossRef Full Text

Wilson, T. D., and Hodges, S. D. (1992). “Attitudes as temporary constructions” in The Construction of Social Judgment, eds L. L. Martin and A. Tesser (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 37–65.

Wilson, T. D., Lindsey, S., and Schooler, J. W. (2000). A model of dual attitudes. Psychol. Rev. 107, 101–126.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wilson, T. D., and Schooler, J. W. (1991). Thinking too much: introspection can reduce the quality of preferences and decisions. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 60, 181–192.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wood, W., and Neal, D. T. (2007). A new look at habits and the habit-goal interface. Psychol. Rev. 14, 843–863.

CrossRef Full Text

Citation: Betsch T (2011) The stability of preferences – a social-cognition view. Front. Psychology 2:290. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00290

Received: 28 June 2011; Accepted: 11 October 2011;
Published online: 15 November 2011.

Copyright: © 2011 Betsch. This is an open-access article subject to a non-exclusive license between the authors and Frontiers Media SA, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in other forums, provided the original authors and source are credited and other Frontiers conditions are complied with.

*Correspondence: tilmann.betsch@uni-erfurt.de

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.