Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 11 February 2014
Sec. Emotion Science

Aesthetic emotions, what are their cognitive functions?

  • Athinoula A. Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Harvard University, Charlestown, MA, USA

Difficulties of Defining “Aesthetic”

A huge number of publications are devoted to aesthetic emotions; Google Scholar gives 319,000 references. Nevertheless, finding a definition of what is aesthetic is not easy. Most authors use no definitions. Wikipedia (2013) gives a circular definition: “aesthetic emotions… are felt during aesthetic activity.” This is similar to the “institutional theory of art” that defines art as what is considered so by an accepted art institution (Dickie, 1974). In 70 years of discussions in the Journal of Aesthetic and Art Criticism this theory, despite its obvious flaws, remains accepted among philosophers of art. Scientists studying emotions should aspire for a more meaningful definition, yet it is not easy to find. For example, Juslin (2013) devotes a special section in his work introducing aesthetic emotions as a fundamental innovation of his theory of musical emotions, yet no definition of aesthetic is given.

Difficulties of contemporary theorists attempting to define “aesthetic” might be related to Kant (1790). He rejected an older idea that aesthetic is related to a special perception ability (Baumgarten, 1992/1750) and attempted to define aesthetic as related to knowledge. This article suggests that Kant came amazingly close to the contemporary scientific understanding, and it clarifies why he could not formulate this idea to his satisfaction. The best he could do is to say that aesthetic emotion is disinterested. On many pages he has repeated that this only concerns everyday mundane interests, that the beautiful is related to some of the most important human interests, that a better definition is needed, but “today” he could not give a satisfactory positive definition of what it is. From Schiller to this very day many discussions continue the false tradition of characterizing aesthetics and beautiful as disinterested (Wikipedia, 2013; Stanford Encyclopedia Stolnitz, 1960; Scruton, 1974, 2007; Guyer, 1997; de Sousa, 2013; Juslin, 2013; Zangwill, 2013; to name just a few among thousands).

This article defines aesthetic and the beautiful in correspondence with Kantian ideas, our deepest intuitions about the beautiful, the Aristotelian “unity in manifold,” (Aristotle, 1995) and in agreement with contemporary understanding of the neural mechanisms of emotions and cognition.

Mathematical Models of Emotions and Cognition

Here is a short summary of this complicated topic, which is an active area of research with thousands of publications; the mathematical model captures essential aspects of the mind mechanisms, it gives many predictions confirmed experimentally and does not contradict known data (more details and references can be found in Perlovsky et al., 2011). This summary is aimed at understanding the mental mechanisms of aesthetic emotions in the next section. Among the most ancient mind mechanisms are instinctual drives. According to the Grossberg and Levine (1987) theory of drives and emotions, instinctual drives can be modeled as internal sensors that measure vital bodily parameters and indicate their safe ranges. If a parameter is outside its safe range, this information is transmitted by neural signals to decision-making parts of the brain-mind initiating appropriate decisions and behavior. These neural signals are perceived internally as emotions motivating behavior. For example, we have sensors measuring the sugar level in blood, when it is below a certain level we feel it as hunger and devote more attention to finding food.

We perceive food and other objects by matching mental representations (memories) of objects to patterns in sensor signals (Kosslyn, 1994). Mental representations are organized into an approximate hierarchy (Grossberg, 1988) from perceptual elements, to objects, to contexts and situations, and higher up to abstract concepts. The evolutionary purpose of evolving the hierarchy is to enable abstract concepts. For example, the representation “professor office” unifies lower-level representations of objects (chair, desk, computer, books) into a unified concept of the office. Similarly, concepts of offices, lecture halls, etc. are unified into a concept of “university,” “educational system,” etc. A neural theory of how information-based pleasure arises from a network involving association cortex, dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, orbitofrontal cortex, striatum, opioids, and dopamine is outlined in Levine (2012). These detailed neural mechanisms of generalized mental representations are not yet accounted for in a simplified mathematical model of interacting emotions and cognition, which misses many details (Pessoa, 2008, 2009), but it is sufficient for the purpose of this article.

The Knowledge Instinct, Aesthetic Emotions, and the Beautiful

The Grossberg and Levine (1987) theory has been extended from bodily needs to learning (Perlovsky, 2001, 2006, 2007, 2008a, 2013a,b; Perlovsky et al., 2011). Satisfaction of bodily needs and our very survival requires understanding of the surrounding world. Therefore, possibly the most important instinct (for humans and higher animals) is an instinct for knowledge, driving learning, knowledge acquisition, and improvement of mental representations for better correspondence to the world. A mathematical model of the knowledge instinct has been discussed in the above references, and candidate neural mechanisms are discussed in Levine and Perlovsky (2008), Levine (2012), Perlovsky and Levine (2012). Similar to other instincts, satisfaction and dissatisfaction of this instinct are perceived emotionally. These specific emotions related to knowledge are called aesthetic emotions. An experimental proof of their existence has been given in Perlovsky et al. (2010).

At lower levels of the mental hierarchy these emotional neural signals are below the conscious threshold. We are not elated with aesthetic pleasure when recognizing an everyday object. However, when we do not recognize familiar objects or situations we immediately perceive these aesthetic emotions, we could become scared. This is one of the standard tricks of thriller movies. At higher levels of the hierarchy we may consciously perceive positive and negative aesthetic emotions. When one solves a problem he or she has been thinking about for a long time, one often feels positive emotions. This is not just a utilitarian emotion due to expecting a salary raise, or being closer to finishing a dissertation. One also feels aesthetic emotions due to satisfaction of the knowledge instinct. The “highest” aesthetic emotion of the beautiful is felt when the knowledge instinct is satisfied at the highest levels of the hierarchy.

Aesthetic Emotions and Contents of the “Highest” Representations

Mental representations at every hierarchical level, as discussed, have an evolutionary purpose to unify lower level representations. The purpose of representations at the top of the hierarchy is to unify one's entire life experience. This unity is felt as the meaning of life; it is important for concentrating one's effort on the most meaningful aims, it is essential for survival, and for achieving the highest goals. For better understanding what this really means we have to go back and consider some details of learning mechanisms.

Mental representations are not as clear and crisp as perceptions of objects. Consider an object in front of your eyes, then close your eyes and imagine this object. The imagination is not as clear as the perception with opened eyes. Imaginations are produced by neural projections of representations to the visual cortex. Vagueness of imaginations testifies to the vagueness of representations. Vagueness of representations has been experimentally demonstrated in brain imaging experiments (Bar et al., 2006; Kveraga et al., 2007; Perlovsky, 2009c). In addition, it has been shown that vaguer representations are also less accessible to consciousness. It follows that abstract representations higher up in the hierarchy, which are based on multiple vague lower level representations, are vague and barely conscious. Their cognitive contents are mixed up with their emotional contents.

However, we can consciously and in detail discuss the meaning of life, and argue for or against its existence. Does this not contradict the above thesis about vagueness and unconsciousness of higher representations? No. And the reason is that language and cognition are separate systems; closely connected, but still separate. Even as we cannot clearly differentiate them in our subjective consciousness, mathematical models of interacting language, cognition, and emotions let us understand how they interact (Perlovsky, 2009a,b, 2013c). Predictions of these models, in particular that abstract concepts are vague, barely conscious, and are understood mostly due to language, are confirmed experimentally (Binder et al., 2005; Price, 2012).

The separateness of language and cognition explains why it is difficult to agree about the meaning of life and the aesthetic emotion of the beautiful. Because these ideas are at the top of the mental hierarchy they are so important (Kant, 1790), for this reason great thinkers for millennia have discussed them, cultures have developed them, and language makes this accumulated knowledge accessible to everyone. But because our subjective perceptions of these ideas are vague, doubts remain. There are no direct subjective conscious confirmations of these cultural constructs, and so far scientific evidence is limited. An important scientific challenge for the near future is to demonstrate that the beautiful is an aesthetic emotion related to satisfaction of the knowledge instinct at the top of the mental hierarchy. Cognitive representations near the top of the hierarchy are vague and unconscious, their contents are “veiled” from our consciousness by language, and therefore “measuring” emotions of the beautiful related to improving these contents is difficult. The beautiful is a rare emotion because the meaning of life is not learned like simple concepts. Most of us can hope for a rare experience confirming that the meaning really exists; at such a moment one experiences emotions of the beautiful.

Multiplicity of Aesthetic Emotions

Human emotional life is rich; we can experience a huge number of emotions, possibly a continuum, not just a few for which we have words, like fear, sadness, joy, etc. The English language has about 150 emotional words, and among these only between 5 and 20 are appreciably different (Petrov et al., 2012). The most advanced scales for rating musical emotions still use emotional words for a few emotions (Zentner et al., 2008). But emotional experiences are much richer than just the few emotions found in English language. The diversity of emotions is most apparent when listening to music; virtually every musical phrase produces a new emotion. What is the origin and cognitive function of the multiplicity of emotions?

The knowledge instinct does not just maximize a single similarity between all representations (knowledge) and all sensor patterns; it acts at every level of the hierarchy, maximizing similarity between bottom-up and top-down signals. In addition it drives the mind to resolve contradictions between knowledge and instinctual drives, and between various elements of knowledge. These contradictions, known as cognitive dissonances (Festinger, 1957; Harmon-Jones et al., 2009), are perceived emotionally. There could be a degree of contradiction between any pair of representation-concepts, and every contradiction is potentially experienced as a separate emotion. People differ in perception of these contradictions and in categorization of corresponding emotions. Still here could be the foundation of a need for diverse emotions. Resolving cognitive contradictions requires abilities for the conscious experience of a large number of emotions. They are needed to maintain diverse knowledge in our minds and for the entire human evolution (see more detailed discussions in Perlovsky, 2008b, 2010, 2012a,b, 2013a). These emotions evolved along with language. As language vocalizations have been losing their emotionality, a separate ability for highly emotional vocalization evolved into music; the still remaining emotionality of language prosody is essential for the continued evolution of languages and cultures (Perlovsky, 2013a,b). Some of these theoretical predictions have been confirmed experimentally (Perlovsky et al., 2010, 2013; Bonniot-Cabanac et al., 2012; Masataka and Perlovsky, 2012, 2013; Cabanac et al., 2013).

Future Research Challenges

Human emotional life is rich; we can experience a huge variety of emotions, most of which are aesthetic. The immediate challenge is to develop experimental techniques for measuring multiplicity of aesthetic emotions. One difficulty is that aesthetic emotions might be subjective and change over time for each individual depending on internal states and external circumstances (e.g., Chapin et al., 2010). Therefore, averaging over individuals often leads to losing fine emotional differentiation and to detecting the most ancient and robust aspects of emotions, valence and arousal. Another difficulty is the use of emotional words in most experimental studies (e.g., Eerola and Vuoskoski, 2011); words are not suitable for measuring emotions inexpressible in words, such as emotions in prosody and music, which evolved for a specific purpose to complement the emotional limitations of language. Detecting a large number of aesthetic emotions, in particular musical emotions, could be approached by subjective estimation of the differences among musical excerpts, and then applying multidimensional scaling to these measures.

Acknowledgments

I am thankful to my colleagues Dan Levine, Angelo Cangelosi, and Yuri Dimitrin for discussions.

References

Aristotle. (1995). The Complete Works. The Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Original work VI BCE.

Bar, M., Kassam, K. S., Ghuman, A. S., Boshyan, J., Schmid, A. M., Dale, A. M., et al. (2006). Top-down facilitation of visual recognition. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 449–454. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0507062103

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Baumgarten, H. (1992/1750). Aesthetica. see in Remembrance of things past: music, autobiographical memory, andemotion. Adv. Consum. Res. 19, 613–620.

Binder, J. R., Westbury, C. F., McKiernan, K. A., Possing, E. T., and Medler, D. A. (2005). Distinct brain systems for processing concrete and abstract concepts. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 17, 1–13. doi: 10.1162/0898929054021102

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., Cabanac, M., Fontanari, F., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012). Instrumentalizing cognitive dissonance emotions. Psychology 3, 1018–1026. doi: 10.4236/psych.2012.312153

CrossRef Full Text

Cabanac, A., Perlovsky, L. I., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., and Cabanac, M. (2013). Music and academic performance. Behav. Brain Res. 256, 257–260. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2013.08.023

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Chapin, H., Jantzen, K., Scott Kelso, J. A., Steinberg, F., and Large, E. (2010). Dynamic emotional and neural responses to music depend on performance expressionand listener experience. PLoS ONE 5:e13812. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0013812

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

de Sousa, R. (2013). “Emotion,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed E. N. Zalta. Available online at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/emotion/

Dickie, G. (1974). “What is art: an institutional analysis,” in The Philosophy of the Visual Art, ed P. H. Alperson (New York: Oxford University Press).

Eerola, T., and Vuoskoski, J. K. (2011). A comparison of the discreteand dimensional models ofemotion in music. Psychol. Music 39, 18–49. doi: 10.1177/0305735610362821

CrossRef Full Text

Festinger, L. (1957). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Grossberg, S. (1988) Nonlinear neural networks: principles, mechanisms, and architectures. Neural Netw. 1, 17–61. doi: 10.1016/0893-6080(88)90021-4

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Grossberg, S., and Levine, D. S. (1987). Neural dynamics of attentionally modulated Pavlovian conditioning: blocking, inter-stimulus interval, and secondary reinforcement. Psychobiology, 15, 195–240.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Guyer, P. (1997). Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Harmon-Jones, E., Amodio, D. M., and HarmonJones, C. (2009). “Action-based model of dissonance: a review, integration, and expansion ofconceptions of cognitive conflict,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, ed M. P. Zanna (Burlington, MA: Academic Press), 119–166.

Juslin, P. N. (2013). From everyday emotions to aesthetic emotions: towards a unified theory of musical emotions. Phys. Life Rev. 10, 235–266. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2013.05.008

CrossRef Full Text

Kant, I. (1790). The Critique of Judgment, Trans. J. H. Bernard. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and Brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Kveraga, K., Boshyan, J., and Bar, M. (2007) Magnocellular projections as the trigger of top-down facilitation in recognition. J. Neurosci. 27, 13232–13240. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3481-07.2007

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Levine, D. S. (2012). “I think therefore I feel: possible neural mechanisms for knowledge-based pleasure,” in The 2012 International Joint Conference on Neural Networks (IJCNN) (Brisbane, QLD), 1–5. doi: 10.1109/IJCNN.2012.6252413

CrossRef Full Text

Levine, D. S., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2008). Neuroscientific insights on biblical myths: simplifying heuristics versus careful thinking: scientific analysis of millennial spiritual issues. Zygon J. Sci. Relig. 43, 797–821. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9744.2008.00961.x

CrossRef Full Text

Masataka, N., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012). The efficacy of musical emotions provoked by Mozart's music for the reconciliation of cognitive dissonance. Sci. Rep. 2, 694. doi: 10.1038/srep00694

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Masataka, N., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2013). Cognitive interference can be mitigated by consonant music and facilitated by dissonant music. Sci. Rep. 3, 2028. doi: 10.1038/srep02028

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2001). Neural Networks and Intellect: Using Model-Based Concepts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Perlovsky, L. I. (2006). Toward physics of the mind: concepts, emotions, consciousness, and symbols. Phys. Life Rev. 3, 22–55. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2005.11.003

CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2007). “Neural dynamic logic of consciousness: the knowledge instinct,” in Neurodynamics of Higher-Level Cognition and Consciousness, eds L. I. Perlovsky and R. Kozma (Heidelberg: Springer Verlag), 73–108. ISBN: 978-3-540-73266-2. doi: 10.1007/978-3-540-73267-9_5

CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2008a). “Sapience, consciousness, and the knowledge instinct (prolegomena to a physical theory),” in Sapient Systems, eds R. Mayorga and L. I. Perlovsky (London: Springer-Verlag), 33–60.

Perlovsky, L. I. (2008b). Music and consciousness, leonardo. J. Arts Sci. Tech. 41, 420–421.

Perlovsky, L. I. (2009a). Language and cognition. Neural Netw. 22, 247–257. doi: 10.1016/j.neunet.2009.03.007

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2009b). Language and emotions: emotional sapir-whorf hypothesis. Neural Netw. 22, 518–526. doi: 10.1016/j.neunet.2009.06.034

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2009c). “Vague-to-Crisp” neural mechanism of perception. IEEE Trans. Neural Netw. 20, 1363–1367. doi: 10.1109/TNN.2009.2025501

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2010). Musical emotions: functions, origin, evolution. Phys. Life Rev. 7, 2–27. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2009.11.001

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2012a). Cognitive function, origin, and evolution of musical emotions. Music. Sci. 16, 185–199. doi: 10.1177/1029864912448327

CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2012b). Cognitive Function of Music, Part I. Interdiscip. Sci. Rev. 37, 129–142. doi: 10.1179/0308018812Z.00000000010

CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013a). A challenge to human evolution—cognitive dissonance. Front. Psychol. 4:179. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00179

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013b). Language and cognition—joint acquisition, dual hierarchy, and emotional prosody. Front. Behav. Neurosci. 7:123. doi: 10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00123

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I. (2013c). Learning in brain and machine-complexity, Gödel, Aristotle. Front. Neurorobot. 7:23. doi: 10.3389/fnbot.2013.00023

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., and Cabanac, M. (2010). Curiosity and Pleasure. WebmedCentral PSYCHOLOGY 2010;1(12):WMC001275. Available online at: http://www.webmedcentral.com/article_view/1275; http://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/1010/1010.3009.pdf

Perlovsky, L. I., Cabanac, A., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C., and Cabanac, M. (2013). Mozart effect, cognitive dissonance, and the pleasure of music. Behav. Brain Res. 244, 9–14. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2013.01.036

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I., Deming R.W., and Ilin, R. (2011). Emotional Cognitive Neural Algorithms with Engineering Applications. Dynamic Logic: from Vague to Crisp. Heidelberg: Springer. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-22830-8

CrossRef Full Text

Perlovsky, L. I., and Levine, D. (2012). The drive for creativity and the escape from creativity: neurocognitive mechanisms. Cogn. Comput. 4, 292–305. doi: 10.1007/s12559-012-9154-3. Available online at: http://www.springerlink.com/content/517un26h46803055/

CrossRef Full Text

Pessoa, L. (2008). On the relationship between emotion and cognition. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 9, 148–158. doi: 10.1038/nrn2317

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Pessoa, L. (2009). How do emotion and motivation direct executive control? Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 160–166. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.01.006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Petrov, S., Fontanari, F., and Perlovsky, L. I. (2012). Subjective emotions vs. verbalizable emotions in web texts. Int. J. Psychol. Behav. Sci. 2, 173–184. doi: 10.5923/j.ijpbs.20120205.08

CrossRef Full Text

Price, C. J. (2012). A review and synthesis of the first 20 years of PET and fMRI studies of heard speech, spoken language and reading. Neuroimage, 62, 816–847. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.04.062

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Scruton, R. (1974). Art and Imagination. London: Routledge.

Scruton, R. (2007). In Search of the aesthetic. Br. J. Aesthet. 47, 232–250. doi: 10.1093/aesthj/aym004

CrossRef Full Text

Stolnitz, J. (1960). “The aesthetic attitude,” in The Philosophy of the Visual Art, ed Ph. Alperson (New York: Oxford University Press), 1992.

Wikipedia. (2013). Available online at: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aesthetic_emotions

Zangwill, N. (2013). “Aesthetic judgment,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/aesthetic-judgment/

Zentner, M., Grandjean, D., and Scherer, K. R. (2008). Emotions evoked by the sound of music: characterization, classification, and measurement. Emotion 8, 494–521. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.8.4.494

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: emotions, aesthetics, beautiful, cognition, music, Kant, mind, mathematical models

Citation: Perlovsky L (2014) Aesthetic emotions, what are their cognitive functions? Front. Psychol. 5:98. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00098

Received: 15 December 2013; Accepted: 24 January 2014;
Published online: 11 February 2014.

Edited by:

Luiz Pessoa, University of Maryland, USA

Reviewed by:

Daniel Saul Levine, University of Texas at Arlington, USA

Copyright © 2014 Perlovsky. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: lperl@rcn.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.