Skip to main content

REVIEW article

Front. Psychol., 14 July 2016
Sec. Psychology of Language

Commentary: “An Evaluation of Universal Grammar and the Phonological Mind”—UG Is Still a Viable Hypothesis

  • Phonology and Reading Laboratory, Department of Psychology, Northeastern University, Boston, MA, USA

Everett (2016b) criticizes The Phonological Mind thesis (Berent, 2013a,b) on logical, methodological and empirical grounds. Most of Everett’s concerns are directed toward the hypothesis that the phonological grammar is constrained by universal grammatical (UG) principles. Contrary to Everett’s logical challenges, here I show that the UG hypothesis is readily falsifiable, that universality is not inconsistent with innateness (Everett’s arguments to the contrary are rooted in a basic confusion of the UG phenotype and the genotype), and that its empirical evaluation does not require a full evolutionary account of language. A detailed analysis of one case study, the syllable hierarchy, presents a specific demonstration that people have knowledge of putatively universal principles that are unattested in their language and these principles are most likely linguistic in nature. Whether Universal Grammar exists remains unknown, but Everett’s arguments hardly undermine the viability of this hypothesis.

The Phonological Mind thesis (Berent, 2013a,b), according to Everett (2016b), is plainly silly. It defends a formal linguistic account that is blatantly false, its experimental support is confounded by trivial “perceptual” factors, and its biological bases are at best tenuous. The problem, according to Everett, is not limited to this particular theory of phonology, or even language. Rather, it is an entire class of nativist accounts of cognition, specifically, the “core knowledge” hypothesis, that is bankrupt. The Phonological Mind thesis, then, exemplifies what has gone so wrong in cognitive nativism.

I believe Everett’s concerns are unfounded. Everett’s broader objections to cognitive nativism are rooted in an erroneous conflation of explanations at the cognitive and biological levels, an implausible view of the links between the cognitive phenotype and the genotype, and a disregard for a large experimental literature that counters his assertions. Similarly, in his attack on The Phonological Mind’s thesis, Everett ignores most of the relevant experimental evidence, he systematically misrepresents my claims, and his characterization of my approach is disingenuous. Whether Universal Grammar exists remains unknown—a fact that (contrary to Everett’s claims) I openly acknowledge. But Everett’s superficial reading of the scientific literature and his incendiary rhetoric do not challenge this hypothesis.

My reply proceeds as follows. I first consider Everett’s broader critique of cognitive nativism and address his logical and methodological concerns about the falsification of nativist claims and their congruency with genetic and evolutionary evidence. Having established some ground rules for testing the core knowledge hypothesis, I proceed to consider the evidence for innate phonological constraints by evaluating the empirical evidence for UG in a particular case study—the restrictions on syllable structure. Everett’s remaining arguments against The Phonological Mind thesis are discussed in the final section. While my reply focuses mostly on the arguments in Everett (2016a), the broader context is set in reference to his upcoming book, Dark Matter of the Mind, of which Everett (2016b) is an excerpt.

Evaluating Cognitive Nativism

To appreciate Everett’s (2016b) critique of nativist theories of language, it is important to consider it within his broader critique of cognitive nativism, specifically, the core knowledge hypothesis. My discussion begins with a brief summary of this hypothesis, followed by a discussion of Everett’s methodological concerns.

The Core Knowledge Hypothesis

Core knowledge theory articulates a cognitive hypothesis regarding the origins of knowledge (for reviews, see Spelke, 1994; Carey and Spelke, 1996; Spelke, 2000; Spelke and Kinzler, 2007; Carey, 2009). It asserts that knowledge is constrained by domain-specific principles that are innate, and consequently, these principles tend to emerge universally, in early development. In addition, core knowledge plays a secondary role in guiding the acquisition of knowledge later in life. For example, young infants (e.g., Feigenson et al., 2002; Wynn et al., 2002; Izard et al., 2009; de Hevia et al., 2014) and animals (e.g., Uller et al., 2001; Flombaum et al., 2005) exhibit a rudimentary understanding of number based on principles that are apparently universal and innate. Unlike the early core knowledge of number, mathematical theory is neither innate nor universal, but its organization appears to follow on the heels of core knowledge principles. Other putative systems of core knowledge concern the representation of objects (e.g., Carey and Xu, 2001), space (e.g., Hermer and Spelke, 1994), others’ minds (e.g., Leslie, 2005) and morality (e.g., Hamlin et al., 2007, 2010). In all cases, infants tend to converge on narrow organizational principles that are apparently unattested in their experience, and these foundations guide the acquisition of related bodies of knowledge later in life (e.g., mathematics, physics, psychology and ethics).

Berent (2013a,b) suggests that phonology might present another core knowledge system, whose organization is constrained by universal grammar. This hypothesis predicts that speakers of all languages converge on shared phonological principles for which they lack inductive basis. To the extent phonological knowledge is abstract, it is possible for it to emerge across language modalities—in signed and spoken phonological systems. Finally, the view of phonology as a system of core knowledge further explains the close links between phonology and reading—a cultural invention that is obviously not universal, but is often phonologically based.

Everett rejects cognitive nativism outright. In his words “There is no human nature if by this we mean a kind of a priori knowledge common to all and only humans” (Everett, 2016a, p. 51)1. “There is nothing like instincts or modules in our higher-level cognitive abilities, e.g., language, interpretative principles of the world around us” (Everett, 2016a, p. 54). But Everett never discusses the details of any of the many experimental studies that demonstrate core knowledge in infancy. Instead, his objections (e.g., to a “moral instinct”) “boil down to three: (i) designer bias (i.e., the appeal to the notion that “humans are the way they are for reasons beyond their control,” p. 660); (ii) Ivy league bias (i.e., “assume the person at the most prestigious university is correct,” p.661); and (iii) simple answers to complex questions” (p. 660). None of these arguments speaks to the experimental evidence itself.

At a broader level, Everett (2016b) outlines two classes of in-principle objections to the core knowledge hypothesis. First, he is worried that this hypothesis is “difficult to falsify”. He next proceeds to attack cognitive nativism based on methodological, genetic and evolutionary considerations. I believe these concerns are unfounded, and I consider them next in turn. My goal here is to demonstrate that cognitive nativism, generally, and phonological nativism, specifically, remains a viable hypothesis. The specific evidence in its support is discussed in Section “A Case Study: The Restrictions on Syllable Structure.”

Falsifying the Core Knowledge Hypothesis: The Cognitive Tests

Contrary to Everett’s worries, the core knowledge hypothesis makes some clear, readily falsifiable claims. This hypothesis would be readily falsified by showing that putative principles of core knowledge either (a) have no effect on behavior; (b) emanate from extraneous sources, external to the domain in question; or (c) are induced (i.e., learned) by tracking the statistical or structural regularities in the child’s experience. In the specific case of phonology, the hypothesis that a principle P forms part of a core phonological system (i.e., universal grammar) would be falsified by either showing that the preference attributed to P is inactive (1) (a), or by showing that it is neither linguistic or innate (i.e., it can be captured by sensorimotor constraints or ones that are induced from experience, see 1b–c).

(1) Falsifying the core knowledge hypothesis. The hypothesis that a principle P forms part of core knowledge of phonology (UG) will be falsified by showing that

(a) P is inactive.

(b) P emanates from extraneous non-phonological sources (e.g., sensorimotor constraints).

(c) P is induced (i.e., learned) by tracking the statistical or structural regularities in the child’s experience.

To illustrate how one can apply these conditions, let us consider in detail one specific example, concerning the putatively universal constraint on syllable structure (i.e., ONSET, Prince and Smolensky, 1993/2004). To reiterate, my goal here is to demonstrate how this constraint can be falsified, in principle; I am not concerned with whether the ONSET hypothesis is correct.

ONSET is a putatively universal phonological principle (P) that requires syllables to have an onset (i.e., begin with a consonant). Accordingly, syllables like pa should be better formed than ap, resulting in a preference for pa across languages, in language processing and acquisition.

(2) ONSET: Syllables must have onsets.

The simplest way to falsify ONSET is to demonstrate that it is inactive in a given language (e.g., English). Notice that counter-examples (i.e., syllables like ap, e.g., ap.pen.dec.to.my) would not necessarily establish that fact. In modern phonological theory (e.g., Prince and Smolensky, 1993/2004; McCarthy and Prince, 1995), all grammatical constraints are violable (an assumption that is independently motivated; for discussion see Prince and Smolensky, 1993/2004; McCarthy and Prince, 1995), so the existence of syllables like ap does not necessarily show that ONSET is inactive. However, one could falsify this hypothesis by documenting a language that actively promotes onsetless syllables (i.e., a preference for a or ap over pa). Some authors have argued that Arrernte presents precisely this case (Breen and Pensalfini, 2001), although the matter remains a topic of controversy (Berry, 1998; Topintzi and Nevins, 2014).

Another way to falsify ONSET is to show that the pa>ap preference is causally determined solely by the relative ease of the perception and articulation of pa. The distinction between a sole direct cause and indirect pressures is absolutely crucial. Many phonological systems conspire to favor forms that optimize speech perception and production—this is precisely what would be expected if phonology were an adaptive biological system (Berent, 2013a,b). But correlation is not causation. The Phonological Mind hypothesis states that sensorimotor pressures constrain the phonological system not in on-line language processing, but rather off-line, in phylogeny—by favoring the biological evolution of abstract universal rules that optimize sensorimotor pressures (e.g., by natural selection, see Figure 1). ONSET presents one such putative constraint. By hypothesis, the ONSET constraint is abstract, so its effect should be independent of the articulatory and acoustic demands associated with the production and perception of specific sounds in a given context (e.g., in clear speech vs. noise), their modality of presentation (e.g., they should be active for both spoken and printed words), and the state of sensorimotor systems (typical or impaired). Demonstrating that phonological principle P can be subsumed by sensorimotor constraints would falsify the hypothesis that P forms part of the core knowledge system of phonology.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 1. The hypothesized links between phonology and the phonetic system. At the heart of the phonological system is the phonological grammar—a set of principles that are abstract and algebraic (as defined in Section Other Objections to the Phonological Mind Thesis), distinct from the phonetic system. Nonetheless, phonetic and sensorimotor pressures shape phonology in language evolution and its acquisition to favor phonological principles that optimize phonetic and sensorimotor pressures.

Learnability presents a third critical test of the hypothesis. A principle P would be falsified if the relevant generalization were induced from experience with similar forms. For example, ONSET would be falsified if the preference for pa (over ap) required experience with syllables like pa, ba, ma, etc. As in the case of sensorimotor correlates, the role of experience must be interpreted with caution. And indeed, the (un)learnability of P does not mean that its acquisition requires no experience at all. It is trivial to show that, absent some minimal triggering conditions, language will not emerge normally. Similarly, absent experience with speech, deaf individuals will develop a sign language, whose phonology is distinct from that of hearing speakers. Experience, then, clearly plays a critical role in triggering the unfolding of the putative phonological phenotype (Berent, 2013a, p. 245). But triggering should not be confused with the cognitive process of inductive learning. The triggering condition entails that the pa preference might require experience with speech, generally. By contrast, induction means that the pa preference will require experience with specific types of syllables—ones whose structural properties overlap with those of the preferred pa type (e.g., labial-initial syllables, such as pa, ba). The hypothesis that certain phonological primitives and constraints are innate cognitive traits (i.e., they arise in the normal course of development, but do not result from a cognitive process; Samuels, 2004) explains this fact.

Evaluation of Innateness at the Behavioral, Genetic and Evolutionary Levels

Our discussion so far shows that the hypothesis of core knowledge is clearly falsifiable, and I believe Everett and I agree on the criteria outlined in (1). In his view, however, the list of methodological requirements for demonstrating core knowledge is more extensive (see 3). In particular, Everett imposes restrictions on the range of admissible experimental methods, and on the genetic and evolutionary conditions for demonstrating core knowledge. I consider these three objections in turn.

(3) Everett’s conditions for demonstrating that principle P forms part of a core knowledge (based on Everett, 2016b, p. 4):

(a) Demonstrate the role of P in infancy by relying on methods “more sound than babies’ sucking or eye-movements.”

(b) “Keep genetics and epigenetics (constraints – embryological, environmental – on the strength, absence, or presence of genetic effects) separate.”

(c) Provide a plausible account for the evolution of the trait.

Everett’s first requirement stipulates conditions on the behavioral methods admissible for demonstrating core knowledge. In his opinion, the support for core knowledge cannot be based on measures involving sucking or eye movement. This requirement arbitrarily rejects a very large literature that demonstrates principles of core knowledge in the first months of life. Everett (2016b) provides no justification for this requirement. Elsewhere (Everett, 2016a, p. 664), he notes the concern that the infant “is acting upon information that is different from the information the researcher is thinking about.” While Everett is of course, right that the link from behavior to cognitive structure is indirect, this challenge is certainly not specific to looking time or sucking methods. Any response to contrasting stimuli—be it manual button press, looking time or neural activity—can only be linked to cognitive structure if those stimuli are matched for all other relevant dimensions. The critical challenge for making such inferences is the control of stimuli, not the modality of response. However, Everett does not show that such controls are lacking in any of the hundreds of studies that employ this procedure. In fact, none of these experimental results is reviewed with any detail. In any case, the evidence for core knowledge in infancy is not limited to looking time or sucking methods. For example, near infrared spectroscopy shows that the brain activity of neonates is modulated by the syllable hierarchy (Gómez et al., 2014). Furthermore, the results from looking time methods are corroborated by findings from brain measures (cf., the evidence for rule learning in behavioral vs. brain measures, in Marcus et al., 1999 and Gervain et al., 2012). Accordingly, the exclusion of the great majority of the infant literature on core knowledge has no justification.

Everett’s next condition requires that one furnish genetic evidence for core knowledge, and in so doing, one must “keep genetics and epigenetics (constraints – embryological, environmental – on the strength, absence, or presence of genetic effects) separate.” To illustrate the logical difficulties inherent in the notion of innate knowledge, Everett considers the “pro-drop” parameter (i.e., optional deletion of the subject, as in “He left”). By his account, each of the two settings of the parameter (i.e., whether or not the subject can be dropped) must each be associated with different genes. Accordingly, if the “pro-drop” parameter were truly innate, then this knowledge must be “located somehow, somewhere in the human genome” (p. 2), and consequently, one would have expected these two settings to doubly dissociate: some genetic mutations should have selectively impaired the acquisition of a “pro-drop” language, but spared a language that lacks the “pro-drop” option; other mutations should have produced the complementary pattern. However, no such dissociations are reported. Beyond this empirical challenge, Everett is concerned that the hypothesis of innate knowledge presents an inherent contradiction. If knowledge (e.g., the “pro-drop” parameter) is genetically coded, then it must be subject to mutations, which would ultimately prevent certain languages from being learnable. In the case of the “pro-drop” parameter, Everett would predict that some language learners should be genetically predisposed toward favoring the “drop” option, whereas others (those carrying the opposite parameter setting) should be predisposed toward learning languages that do not drop their subject. The result is that “not all people may be able to learn every language” (p. 2). Put differently, if UG is innate, then it cannot be universal.

However, there are a number of fallacies in this logic. First, innateness and universality are not an oxymoron. Humans are innately equipped with two eyes, yet this trait does not become abruptly extinct (i.e., non-universal) in the population by sudden spontaneous mutations. This is because innate traits are buffered by homeostatic mechanisms that seek to detect and correct replication errors in the genome, as well as cell and tissue malfunctions during embryonic development. These checks and balances are not infallible. Accordingly, rare genetic abnormalities or developmental problems (like the loss of particular cell types or interference from external factors that embryos can be exposed to, such as alcohol, nicotine, synthetic steroid hormones, etc.) could prevent the typical acquisition of universal grammar, just as they can result in a single “cyclopean” eye in human fetuses (Sarnat et al., 2014). Such rare cases of dysfunction do not throw into question the reality of the complex sequence of developmental events that forms the innate basis of the “two eyes” trait and its universality in the normal population. The same holds for universal grammar.

Similarly, there is no biological reason that distinct settings of a UG principle (e.g., “pro-drop”) must doubly dissociate. Everett predicts such dissociations because he believes that distinct innate principles (e.g., the two settings of the “pro-drop” parameter) must be “localized” in distinct bits of DNA. But this requirement is based on a misunderstanding of the relation between genotypes and phenotypes. Core knowledge (e.g., UG) concerns properties of the cognitive phenotype—the putative set of cognitive principles that are somehow represented in the brains of individual speakers; this is not conceptually identical to the genotype of these individuals (e.g., their particular sequences of DNA bases), nor are genotypes and phenotypes necessarily related in a one-to-one fashion. By hypothesis, the tendency of humans to converge on a cognitive phenotypic trait is constrained by their genome, but the links between the phenotype and genotype are complex. For example, the “blue eye” and “brown eye” phenotypes are not expressed on distinct genes; rather, eye color is a complex genetic trait that is linked to multiple single nucleotide polymorphisms that do not sum up in a linear, additive fashion (e.g., Liu et al., 2009). Likewise, the expression of innate traits is inextricably linked to epigenetic factors (Ridley, 2003) as well as chance events (Balaban, 2006). Language (e.g., the “pro-drop” parameter) is unlikely to form an exception.

None of the above, however, means that the hypothesis of (innate) core knowledge is vacuous or untestable. Rather, these facts remind us that innateness is a multifaceted problem that can be evaluated at different levels of analysis. Genetics and the cognitive sciences represent two very different levels. Critically, it is both unreasonable and biologically unrealistic to expect direct, one-to-one mapping across these levels (Balaban, 2006). The problem of collapsing across levels of analysis is hardly unique to the cognitive sciences. Chemical reactions, for instance, attain different explanations in the fields of physics and chemistry, and it is impossible to reduce one level of analysis to the other (Chomsky, 2014). In short, scientific hypotheses can be evaluated only at the level of analysis to which they apply (Fodor and Pylyshyn, 1988; Samuels, 2004; Chomsky, 2014; see also Berent, 2013a; Embick and Poeppel, 2015), and in the case of core knowledge, this is squarely within the cognitive level. Everett would be entirely right to expect cognitive scientists to separate the role of innate principles and learning at the cognitive level. However, it does not follow that each cognitive trait will be transparently mapped to distinct bits of DNA, irrespective of epigenetic factors. Everett’s insistence on “locating” UG principles in the genome and “separating genetics from epigenetics” is a red herring, rooted in the erroneous conflation of the cognitive and genetic levels of analysis.

Everett’s final condition, his demand for a complete evolutionary history of core knowledge, is another such diversionary tactic. Everett is of course right to urge us to explore the evolution of core (phonological) knowledge—a question Berent (2013a) examines by conducting an in-depth analysis of the precursors of phonological principles in non-humans (see Chapter 10). But a detailed evolutionary history is by no means a logical prerequisite for establishing that core knowledge exists. To reiterate, the core knowledge hypothesis is first a claim concerning the synchronic cognitive state of individual speakers. We now turn to evaluating the empirical evidence for its support in the case of phonology.

A Case Study: The Restrictions on Syllable Structure

The Phonological Mind examines the origins of phonological primitives and constraints by reviewing the empirical evidence in multiple case studies using a broad interdisciplinary perspective, informed by linguistic analysis, behavioral experiments with adults and children, and neuroimaging studies. In most of these cases, the conclusions are unclear—a fact that I openly acknowledge (contrary to Everett’s assertions). One such case, however, has been the subject of systematic investigation that directly pits the UG account against various non-linguistic explanations (per the requirements in 1a-c above). Accordingly, this case features prominently in Berent (2013a) and it forms the center of Everett’s (2016b) critique. I will first describe the linguistic phenomenon at hand and the experimental evidence, and then consider Everett’s objections.

The Linguistic Phenomenon

Across languages, certain syllable types are systematically preferred to others. Syllables like bla, with stop-liquid onsets, are preferred (e.g., more frequent) relative to bna (i.e., stop-nasal combinations), which, in turn, are preferred to bda (two stops); least preferred are syllables like lba (i.e., liquid-stop sequences); together those preferences give rise to a syllable hierarchy (see 4). Such preferences have been documented statistically in the distribution of these syllables in language surveys (Greenberg, 1978; Berent et al., 2007), so their existence is well established. The question is whether those facts reflect linguistic principles that are active universally, in the grammar of every individual speaker.

(4) The syllable hierarchy: blif>bnif>bdif>lbif

Everett strategically diverts the discussion of this cognitive question by plunging into a technical linguistic controversy concerning one formal analysis of this phenomenon, the sonority sequencing generalization (SSG, for definition, see Box 1; see also Saussure, 1915/1959; Vennemann, 1972; Hooper, 1976; Kiparsky, 1979; Steriade, 1982; Selkirk, 1984; Clements, 1990; Gouskova, 2001; de Lacy, 2004; Smolensky, 2006; Zec, 2007). In so doing, he hopes to discredit the hypothesis that the syllable hierarchy is universal. Everett asserts that sonority is a circular concept that is devoid of phonetic basis, and he marshals a number of challenges to this analysis. But many of these challenges are erroneous (see Box 1). His exposition of the linguistic literature (based on Ohala’s seminal work from the Ohala, 1990) ignores more recent developments in phonetics (Parker, 2002) and phonology (e.g., Parker, 2012, and chapters therein). Furthermore, Everett overlooks the fact that the SSG correctly generates additional predictions regarding several other syllable hierarchies (see 6), and these predictions are borne out by both linguistic and experimental evidence (e.g., Berent et al., 2009, 2010, 2011b, 2012a; Lennertz and Berent, 2015; Tamasi and Berent, 2015).

Box 1. Everett’s critique of sonority.

An influential account of the syllable hierarchy appeals to sonority. Sonority is an abstract phonological property that correlates with the loudness of phonological elements (Clements, 1990; Zec, 2007; Parker, 2008, 2012). On a basic sonority scale (Clements, 1990), the most sonorous (e.g., loudest) consonants are glides (e.g., w, y; with a sonority (s) of 4), followed by liquids (e.g., l, r; s = 3), nasals (e.g., m, n; s = 2) and obstruents (e.g., b, p; s = 1). Using these levels, one can calculate the sonority distance in the onset by subtracting the sonority level of the first onset consonant from that of the second (Δs = s2-s1, see 5). Accordingly, syllables like bla exhibit a large rise in sonority (s = Δ2) and bna exhibits a smaller rise (Δs = 1), whereas lba exhibits sonority fall (Δ2 = -2). Indeed, as the sonority cline decreases, the syllable becomes underrepresented across languages (Berent et al., 2007). Thus, blif, for instance, is more frequent than bnif, which is more frequent than bdif; least frequent are syllables like lbif.

(5) The sonority distance in complex onsets

www.frontiersin.org

This observation is captured by a constraint on syllable structure known as the sonority sequencing generalization (SSG). The SSG states that onsets must rise in sonority, whereas codas must exhibit a sonority fall. A related principle, the minimal sonority distance, states that languages restrict the minimal sonority distance they allow; English, for instance, requires a rise of at least two steps, so it allows syllables like bla (Δs = 2), but bans syllables like bdas = 0). Smolensky (2006) further shows that the preference for syllables with large sonority distances can be traced to putatively universal constraints.

Everett amasses several challenges to the SSG; some are justified, but most are not. For example, Everett notes that the sonority hierarchy does not explain the ban on English syllables such as bwa, or account for the aversion to syllables like /ji/ across languages. However, these observations are fully in line with the SSG. Considering the English ban on bwa, Everett is right to note that the SSG should render such a syllable well formed in English (as its sonority distance, Δs = 2, is comparable to twin, for instance). However, this does not show that the SSG is wrong. Indeed, no single phonological constraint can single-handedly capture the entire phonology. In the case of bwa, its avoidance is due to an independently motivated constraint that bans adjacent identical features (i.e., the adjacent labials in bwa, which are banned by the Obligatory Contour Principle, McCarthy, 1994), so this fact has no bearing on the SSG. The second observation—the aversion to /ji/ across language—actually follows from the SSG. Because these glide-vowel sequences exhibit a minimal sonority rise, they are expected to be dispreferred. These facts present an embarrassment to Everett’s linguistic analysis, not to the SSG.

Other facts (e.g., the allowance of English syllables like spot), however, are known counterexamples to the SSG. Since English typically requires its syllables to exhibit a rise of two steps in sonority, plateaus such as spot should have been unattested. While this fact is amenable to a formal explanation (Selkirk, 1982), s-initial onsets present a systematic counter-example to the sonority hierarchy in many languages, and, contrary to Everett’s accusations, I have openly acknowledged these challenges in print (Berent et al., 2007; Berent, 2013a, p. 167).

(6) Other syllable hierarchies predicted by the SSG:

(a) mla>mda

(b) fsa>fta

These challenges notwithstanding, the concept of sonority is still attractive because it generates a number of correct predictions regarding several other hierarchies. For example, the sonority hierarchy correctly predicts a preference for nasal-sonorant over nasal-stop onsets (e.g., for mlif over mdif). Similarly, a more detailed (and independently motivated, Steriade, 1982) sonority scale that renders fricatives more sonorous than stops predicts a preference for fsik (a fricative-fricative onset, i.e., a sonority plateau) over ftik (a fricative-stop onset, i.e., a very small fall in sonority). These results are borne out by experimental evidence (e.g., Berent et al., 2009, 2010, 2011b, 2012a; Lennertz and Berent, 2015; Tamasi and Berent, 2015). For reasons of space, my discussion of the sonority hierarchy focuses only on the stop-sonorant sequence in (1), but these other hierarchies should be kept in mind.

While there is much evidence to suggest that the SSG merits careful consideration, it is important to keep in mind that the SSG and the syllable hierarchy are not one and the same. The syllable hierarchy is a hypothesis concerning speakers’ grammatical preferences; the SSG presents a particular account of the formal mechanisms that give rise to these preferences. Other formal accounts, however, can capture the hierarchy without appealing to sonority (e.g., Smolensky, 2006, and its discussion in Berent, 2013a, pp. 172–174). So even if the SSG should turn out to be wrong (a question that is still very much open), the syllable hierarchy could still remain viable. It is the syllable hierarchy, then, not the SSG, that is the topic of our discussion. We now turn to examining the relevant experimental evidence.

The Experimental Evidence

My colleagues and I have examined the hypothesis that the syllable hierarchy (as in 4), as well as the related hierarchies (see 6) is the product of universal grammatical constraints (Berent et al., 2007, 2008, 2009, 2010, 2011a,b, 2012a, 2013b, 2014, 2015; Gómez et al., 2014; Lennertz and Berent, 2015; Tamasi and Berent, 2015; Zhao and Berent, 2015).

Our research program proceeds in two steps. First, we ask whether speakers are sensitive to the structure of syllables that they have never heard before. For example, do English speakers favor bnif to bdif, and bdif to lbif despite the fact that none of these syllable types exists in their language? To the extent that such preferences are detected, we next examine whether they result from universal grammatical constraints, or from various non-grammatical sources—auditory, articulatory, or lexical.

(7) Testing the syllable hierarchy:

(a) Ill-formed syllables are systematically misidentified—the worse formed the syllable, the more likely its misidentification.

(b) The misidentification of ill-formed syllables is inexplicable by non-grammatical sources, including:

(i) Auditory/phonetic failure

(ii) Articulatory difficulty

(iii) Similarity to familiar syllables

To infer people’s preferences, we exploit the phenomenon of grammatical repair. We reason that, if all grammars universally encode the syllable hierarchy, then ill-formed syllables will not be represented faithfully. Instead, ill-formed syllables (e.g., lbif) will be recoded (i.e., repaired) by the grammar as better-formed syllables (e.g., as lebif). Repair, then, can potentially provide a litmus test for the ill-formedness of a syllable. And if ill-formedness depends on the syllable hierarchy, then this hierarchy should determine the likelihood of repair—the worse formed the syllable, the more likely its repair, hence, its misidentification. These predictions are borne out by numerous studies with speakers of various languages. Figure 2 summarizes results from speakers of English (Berent et al., 2007), Spanish (Berent et al., 2012b) and Korean (Berent et al., 2008).

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 2. The effect of the syllable hierarchy on responses to monosyllables by speakers of English, Spanish, and Korean. Participants in this task indicate whether the auditory input has one syllable or two. Results show that worse-formed syllables elicit more errors. Error bars are confidence intervals for the difference between the means. Data from Experiment 1 in Berent et al. (2007, 2008, 2012b).

Obviously, misidentification can also emerge from many other sources (see Figure 3). In particular, syllables like lbif could be misidentified because people fail to extract their phonetic form from the auditory signal (Davidson and Shaw, 2012; Wilson et al., 2014). Similarly, syllables like lbif might exert greater articulatory demands. Given the known links between speech perception and articulatory action (Fadiga et al., 2002; Pulvermüller et al., 2006), the misidentification of lbif in perception could result from difficulties in its covert production (Redford, 2008). Finally, it is conceivable that the syllable hierarchy in (4) is encoded in the phonological grammar of some speakers due to experience with similar syllables in their language (e.g., Daland et al., 2011). Accordingly, the attribution of misidentification to core knowledge of phonology (i.e., UG) can only be done by elimination—after rejecting non-phonological (acoustic and articulatory) and inductive sources, as indicated in (1) above.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 3. Potential sources of misidentification. According to the phonological account, ill-formed syllables (e.g., lba) are misidentified because they are repaired by the grammar due to their violation of universal grammatical constraints. Misidentification, in this view, is due to phonological repair, occurring during phonological encoding. However, by alternative accounts, misidentification results from the dissimilarity of the input to the lexicon, or difficulties in its phonetic encoding, due to failure either to extract its auditory/phonetic form, or to covertly simulate its articulation.

My colleagues and I have addressed each of these alternative explanations in turn. Contrary to the phonetic/auditory explanation, we found that ill-formed syllables do not present greater processing cost under conditions that promote attention to the phonetic properties of the stimuli (e.g., Berent et al., 2007, Experiments 5–6; Berent et al., 2012a). This finding challenges the assertion that such syllables are misidentified because they are harder to encode at the phonetic/auditory level. Furthermore, the (phonological) difficulties in processing ill-formed syllables persist when the stimuli are presented in print—in the absence of any phonetic/auditory demands whatsoever (see Figure 4A; Berent, 2008; Berent et al., 2009; Berent and Lennertz, 2010; Tamasi and Berent, 2015).

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 4. Tests of non-grammatical explanations for the misidentification of ill-formed syllables. (A) Sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy with printed materials. In this task, people make identity judgment (e.g., is lbif = LEBIF?). Results show that, as the syllable becomes worse formed, people take longer to discriminate monosyllables from their disyllabic counterparts. (B) Sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy despite suppression of the lip motor by TMS. Results show that TMS attenuates overall discrimination (d′), but it does not diminish the sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy. (C,D) Sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy in neonates. Results plot the effect of the syllable hierarchy on differences in oxyhemoglobin (red) and deoxyhemoglobin (blue) concentration changes for ill-formed minus well-formed syllables, contrasting either (C) sonority rises and falls (e.g., blif vs. lbif) or (D) sonority rises and plateaus (e.g., blif vs. bdif) at four regions of interest (superior and inferior at the left and right hemisphere; * indicates significant differences, p < 0.05). (E) The effect of the syllable hierarchy on the posterior part of Broca’s area: as the syllable becomes ill-formed, activation increases (data from Berent et al., 2014).

Our results are likewise inconsistent with an articulatory explanation. If the difficulties in processing ill-formed syllables result from difficulty in their subvocal articulation, then procedures that suppress the articulatory motor system should attenuate the disadvantage of ill-formed syllables. Contrary to the articulatory account, however, we found that ill-formed syllables are misidentified even when articulation is suppressed—either mechanically, by having participants bite on tongue depressors (Zhao, 2015), or electromagnetically, by disrupting the lip motor area in the brain using transcranial magnetic stimulation (Berent et al., 2015). Additional evidence for an abstract grammatical locus of repair is presented by neurological patients, whose repair of onset clusters in production is demonstrably distinct from sensorimotor pressures (Buchwald et al., 2007; Buchwald, 2009; Cohen-Goldberg et al., 2013; Miozzo and Buchwald, 2013).

Finally, several studies counter the lexical analogy explanation—the possibility that bnif is preferred solely for its similarity to sniff, for instance. We find that sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy obtains even in languages that arguably lack complex onsets of any type (for Korean see Berent et al., 2008; for Mandarin Chinese, Zhao and Berent, 2015), and even in the absence of any lexicon at all—among neonates (Gómez et al., 2014, see Figure 4). These findings from neonates agree with the outcomes from an imaging study with adults (Berent et al., 2014) showing that ill-formed syllables elicit a monotonic increase in the activation of the posterior part of Broca’s area (BA 45, see Figure 4D). Together, these results suggest that syllable structure is constrained by abstract grammatical principles that are broadly shared across languages, possibly universally. The repair of ill-formed syllables results from their violation.

Everett’s Objections to the Empirical Findings

Given the large experimental literature that has examined the syllable hierarchy, one would expect a critique to scrutinize the experimental logic, methods, statistical analysis or results of specific studies. However, Everett (2016a,b) cites none of those primary sources. In fact, he hardly acknowledges that any of these studies has even attempted to address any non-grammatical explanation for the results. Instead, his exposition reduces the experimental logic ad ridiculum to the following: if people misidentify lbif, ergo, the SSG is an instinct.

Patient readers must endure the bulk of his critique to learn that the actual rationale guiding the experimental investigation is far more nuanced, and those non-phonological (and non-universal) sources for the syllable hierarchy have been carefully considered and evaluated experimentally. Even then, however, Everett’s description hardly does justice to the research program as a whole. For example, he briefly acknowledges that the syllable hierarchy has been replicated in silent reading (contrary to the auditory/phonetic account), but then immediately moves to dismiss these results on grounds that “we know too little about the relationship between speaking and reading” (Everett, 2016b, p. 7). These alleged gaps, however, do not stop Everett from offering an original reading theory of his own (Everett, 2016b, pp. 7–8; italics mine):

...in looking at new words speakers often try to create the phonology in their heads and so this “silent pronunciation” could guide such speakers’ choices, etc. Everyone (modulo pathology) has roughly the same ears matched to roughly the same vocal apparatus. Thus although phonologies can grammaticalize violations of functionally preferable phonotactic constraints, one would expect that in experiments that clearly dissociate the experimental data from the speaker’s own language, the functionality of the structures, e.g., being auditorily easier to distinguish, will emerge as decisive factors, accounting for speakers’ reactions to non-native sequences that respect or violate sonority sequencing, etc. In fact, there is a name for this, though with a somewhat different emphasis, in Optimality Theoretic Phonology (Prince and Smolensky, 1993/2004; McCarthy and Prince, 1994) – the “emergence of the unmarked.”

This passage is striking for various reasons. First, it is puzzling to see the liberty Everett takes in dismissing the huge literature on reading, which suggests (based on behavioral results and evidence from neuroimaging) that speakers are acutely sensitive to the phonological structure of printed words (for reviews: Perfetti, 1985; Van Orden et al., 1990; Berent and Perfetti, 1995). Reading, to be sure, is not the only experimental literature to be singlehandedly rejected by Everett—recall that he also dismisses the entire infancy literature of sucking/looking time. This is a peculiar move from a serious scholar who is committed to “empirical adequacy.”

Moving to Everett’s own reading theory, it is unclear how, in this proposal, auditory constraints come to shape speakers’ behavior. Surely, people cannot possibly misidentify the printed word lbif because this stimulus imposes excessive auditory demands; perhaps Everett is suggesting that people estimate the demands auditory stimuli might impose, and use this estimate to inform their judgments. However, there is no evidence that such a mechanism exists, let alone that it can estimate the demands of unfamiliar stimuli. Either way, misidentification, by this account, would reflect the outcome of a process that estimates the demands on speech perception, not a perceptual mechanism (auditory or phonetic). Alternatively, perhaps the syllable hierarchy reflects principles that are inferred on the fly. Everett implies that a single encounter with an unfamiliar stimulus results in the emergence of phonological constraints, a phenomenon he attributes to the The Emergence of the Unmarked (referring to a central outcome of Optimality theory, McCarthy and Prince, 1994). But The Emergence of the Unmarked (at least according to McCarthy and Prince, 1994) is due to innate, universal grammatical constraints, not auditory difficulties. And if such constraints were active, then this would support the UG account, rather than disprove it.

In any case, the existing experimental evidence against the auditory account is not limited to findings from printed materials. Other results show that, when prompted to attend to phonetic detail, people do not necessarily experience greater difficulties with ill-formed syllables (Berent et al., 2007, 2012a). Likewise, individuals with dyslexia, whose auditory and phonetic systems are demonstrably impaired, exhibit intact sensitivity to the syllable hierarchy (Berent et al., 2013b, 2016). These two sets of results are important because they suggest that the misidentification of ill-formed syllables is rooted in the phonological, rather than the phonetic or auditory systems.

Summary

Everett’s critique centers on a specific formal analysis of the syllable hierarchy (SSG), not the evidence for the hierarchy itself, and for the most part, his formal objections are erroneous. His only objection to the experimental findings is based on an incoherent model of silent reading for which there is no support. I thus conclude that Everett’s attack on the syllable hierarchy is unfounded.

Other Objections to The Phonological Mind Thesis

Anticipating the shortcomings of his own attack on the syllable hierarchy, Everett declares that even if the SSG were to be replaced by more adequate formal principles, the “core knowledge” hypothesis would still crumble. This is because “the evidence she (IB) provides for an instinct fails no matter what principle she might appeal to” (p. 7). In support of this assertion, Everett submits that all other hallmarks (actual or presumed) of core knowledge in phonology need not arise from any innate universal principles. Specifically, he asserts that algebraic rules can be learned from experience, and that the properties of phonological systems (unique shared design, early onset, and spontaneous regenesis) can all be traced to sensorimotor, rather than phonological pressures. The regenesis of signed phonological systems, in Everett’s view, is irrelevant to spoken phonology, and the early onset of spoken phonology simply reflects rapid learning. Finally, scaffolding (the propensity of phonological systems to give rise to reading) is simultaneously false and non-specific to phonology. Once again, however, Everett’s anti-nativist fervor clouds some critical scientific nuances.

(8) Other evidence against core knowledge of phonology:

(a) Algebraic rules are learned from experience.

(b) The unique, shared design of phonological systems, their early onset in development and their spontaneous regenesis are all explained by sensorimotor pressures, not principles specific to phonology.

(c) Regenesis establishes a false analogy between signed and spoken phonology.

(d) The early onset of phonology reflects early learning.

(e) Scaffolding is both false and not specific to phonology.

Everett’s attack on algebraic rules conflates two very different hypotheses about (a) the computational properties of linguistic rules (i.e., the algebraic hypothesis) and (b) the origins of some rules (i.e., the Universal Grammar hypothesis), which together form the thesis of The Phonological Mind (see 9).

(9) The Phonological Mind thesis:

(a) The algebraic hypothesis (Computation): The phonological grammar consists of algebraic rules.

(b) The universal grammar hypothesis (Origins): Some grammatical primitives and constraints are innate.

The algebraic hypothesis asserts that phonological principles apply over abstract categories (e.g., “consonant”) rather than their members (e.g., the consonant b or k), such that all category members are treated alike (i.e., they form equivalence classes). Furthermore, the grammar encompasses mechanisms that operate over entire categories using variables (e.g., X, standing for “any consonant”) and, consequently, grammatical rules can encode abstract relations among categories (e.g., identity, recursion). For example, the XXY rule (where X and Y stand for any two consonants) bans any XXY form, that is, any tri-consonantal structure with identical consonants at its beginning, regardless of whether these consonants are familiar or novel. The hypothesis that some grammatical rules are innate (i.e., the universal grammar hypothesis) is a second hypothesis that is logically distinct from the algebraic hypothesis. Everett attacks the algebraic hypothesis because algebraic rules, such as the Semitic ban on XXY stems (Greenberg, 1950), are learned in many cognitive domains. However, the algebraic hypothesis makes no claims about the innateness of any particular phonological rule or its domain specificity. Everett’s attack confounds the algebraic and UG claims.

The algebraic hypothesis is critical for two reasons. First, it explains productivity—the capacity of the grammar to generalize phonological principles across the board, to any member of a class (e.g., even to non-native consonants). Second, it allows one to draw a principled distinction between the (algebraic) phonological grammar, and the (non-algebraic, analog) phonetic and sensorimotor systems (see Figure 1). This distinction becomes particularly significant in light of Everett’s subsequent argument that phonological pressures are sensorimotor. Obviously, if phonological systems were to directly reflect analog sensorimotor pressures, then, ipso facto, such systems could not possibly be phonological (i.e., algebraic); they would be sensorimotor. Nonetheless, Everett is right to note that many phonological principles “conspire” to favor structures that optimize sensorimotor pressures. The Phonological Mind captures both the distinction between these two systems (phonology and the sensorimotor system) as well as their convergence. The distinction between the phonology and the sensorimotor systems is explained by the hypothesis that the two systems are distinct, and they differ in their computational properties. Their convergence is explained by the hypothesis that sensorimotor pressures shape the design of the phonological system in phylogeny (Berent, 2013a,b, see Figure 1). To reiterate, the correlation between phonology and sensorimotor pressures does not necessarily mean causation affecting on-line, language processing.

The hypothesis that some phonological principles are both algebraic (i.e., abstract and amodal) and innate would explain the capacity of phonological systems to emerge spontaneously in a new linguistic modality, in nascent sign language (i.e., regenesis: see 8c, e.g., Sandler et al., 2011; Brentari et al., 2012; Coppola and Brentari, 2014). The same hypothesis would also account for the early emergence of phonology in typical language development.

Everett rejects the evidence from regenesis because “no one has ever successfully demonstrated that signed languages have “phonology” in the same sense as spoken languages” (p. 8). It is unclear what Everett means by “successfully,” as there is certainly ample research to suggest that significant cross-modal phonological similarities exist. For example, as with spoken languages, signers encode syllables and constrain their internal structure by appealing to their sonority (defined by the visual salience of phonological features, e.g., Perlmutter, 1992; Brentari, 1993; Sandler, 1993; Williams and Newman, 2016). Furthermore, experimental evidence shows that English speakers spontaneously extend their phonological knowledge of syllable structure to signs (Berent et al., 2013a). Clearly, phonology is not confined to spoken languages.

Everett’s next stipulation, that the early onset of phonology in typical development is entirely due to rapid learning (8d), is likewise countered by evidence for the syllable hierarchy in neonates (Gómez et al., 2014). While knowledge seen at birth can be learned—fetuses are known to extract rhythmical properties of their maternal language in utero (e.g., Kisilevsky et al., 2009)—it is unlikely that such learning would extend to specific consonantal features. Indeed, infants do not show knowledge of the specific phonetic contrasts of their mothers’ languages until the end of their first year of life (e.g., Eimas et al., 1971; Werker and Tees, 1984). The findings of Gómez et al. (2014) do not establish what principles guide neonates’ preferences (e.g., phonological vs. phonetic). Nonetheless, neonates’ sensitivity to syllable structure is likely innate.

Moving to his last point (8e), Everett rejects scaffolding—the hypothesis innate core knowledge forms the basis for related bodies of knowledge that are acquired in later development. For example, the (innate, universal) core knowledge of number forms the basis for the recursive number system that emerges optionally in later development. In a similar vein, the putative innate knowledge of phonology could explain the fact that mature writing systems tend to encode phonological principles, and reading tends to recover phonological structure from print.

Everett objects on grounds that scaffolding is both (a) not specific to phonology and (b) false, since some writing systems are hieroglyphic. However, these claims are both self-contradictory and individually unwarranted. Scaffolding does not mean that every writing system ever invented is phonological. Rather, phonology appears to impose a constraint on the cultural evolution of writing systems, such that mature writing systems tend to encode phonological units (DeFrancis, 1989), and readers tend to automatically recover these phonological representations from print (for discussion, see Perfetti, 1985; Van Orden et al., 1990; Berent and Perfetti, 1995). Similarly, Everett’s first objection (“scaffolding is non-unique”) attacks a straw man. No one claims that scaffolding is a defining feature (i.e., a necessary and sufficient condition) of core knowledge, so Everett is right to note that these properties are also found in systems that are clearly invented by culture (“Burrito-making has its own unique features,” p. 8). However, while Everett may admire the unique design of burritos, enthusiasm for this observation is tempered by the fact that, unlike phonology, burrito design is neither universal, early nor spontaneously emerging. The conjunction of these features is suggestive of core knowledge.

Conclusion

Everett is certainly right to question whether phonology is a system of core knowledge. I applaud his efforts to unveil the origins of language and his many contributions to the field. Summarizing the state of research in The Phonological Mind, I concluded, “While the core phonology proposal seems to presently offer the best explanation for the wide range of evidence considered in this book, the available evidence is insufficient to fully evaluate this hypothesis,” and I proceeded to indicate a number of open questions for future research (Berent, 2013a, p. 312). Resolution of these issues will require a nuanced theoretical analysis followed by careful experimental scrutiny. Inflammatory statements only hinder the progress of this enterprise. As Everett puts it, “… a spurious observation of a few phonologists is not likely to serve as an instinct” (Everett, 2016b, p. 6). Neither, by the same token, could such remarks possibly refute this hypothesis.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Funding

This research was supported by an NSF award 1528411.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Evan Balaban and Joanne Miller for their comments on this manuscript, and for Nancy Frost, for copyediting. All remaining errors are mine.

Footnotes

  1. ^ All page citations of Everett (2016a) are based on a manuscript from August 03, 2015.

References

Balaban, E. (2006). Cognitive developmental biology: history, process and fortune’s wheel. Cognition 101, 298–332. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2006.04.006

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I. (2008). Are phonological representations of printed and spoken language isomorphic? Evidence from the restrictions on unattested onsets. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 34, 1288–1304. doi: 10.1037/0096-1523.34.5.1288

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I. (2013a). The Phonological Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Berent, I. (2013b). The phonological mind. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17, 319–327. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2013.05.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Balaban, E., Lennertz, T., and Vaknin-Nusbaum, V. (2010). Phonological universals constrain the processing of nonspeech. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 139, 418–435. doi: 10.1037/a0020094

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Brem, A.-K., Zhao, X., Seligson, E., Pan, H., Epstein, J., et al. (2015). Role of the motor system in language knowledge. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 112, 1983–1988. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1416851112

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Dupuis, A., and Brentari, D. (2013a). Amodal aspects of linguistic design. PLoS ONE 8:e60617. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0060617

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Harder, K., and Lennertz, T. (2011a). Phonological universals in early childhood: evidence from sonority restrictions. Lang. Acquis. 18, 281–293. doi: 10.1080/10489223.2011.580676

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., and Lennertz, T. (2010). Universal constraints on the sound structure of language: phonological or acoustic? J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 36, 212–223. doi: 10.1037/a0017638

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Lennertz, T., and Balaban, E. (2012a). Language universals and misidentification: a two way street. Lang. Speech 55, 1–20. doi: 10.1177/0023830911417804

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Lennertz, T., Jun, J., Moreno, M. A., and Smolensky, P. (2008). Language universals in human brains. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105, 5321–5325. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0801469105

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Lennertz, T., and Rosselli, M. (2012b). Universal phonological restrictions and language-specific repairs: evidence from Spanish. Ment. Lex. 13, 275–305. doi: 10.1075/ml.7.3.02ber

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Lennertz, T., and Smolensky, P. (2011b). “Markedness and misperception: It’s a two-way street,” in Handbook of the Syllable, eds C. E. Cairns and E. Raimy (Leiden: Brill), 373–394.

Google Scholar

Berent, I., Lennertz, T., Smolensky, P., and Vaknin-Nusbaum, V. (2009). Listeners’ knowledge of phonological universals: evidence from nasal clusters. Phonology 26, 75–108. doi: 10.1017/S0952675709001729

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Pan, H., Zhao, X., Epstein, J., Bennett, M. L., Deshpande, V., et al. (2014). Language universals engage Broca’s area. PLoS ONE 9:e95155. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0095155

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., and Perfetti, C. A. (1995). A rose is a REEZ: the two cycles model of phonology assembly in reading English. Psychol. Rev. 102, 146–184. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.102.1.146

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Steriade, D., Lennertz, T., and Vaknin, V. (2007). What we know about what we have never heard: evidence from perceptual illusions. Cognition 104, 591–630. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2006.05.015

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Vaknin-Nusbaum, V., Balaban, E., and Galaburda, A. (2013b). Phonological generalizations in dyslexia: the phonological grammar may not be impaired. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 30, 285–310. doi: 10.1080/02643294.2013.863182

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berent, I., Zhao, X., Balaban, E., and Galaburda, A. M. (2016). Phonology and phonetics dissociate in dyslexia: evidence from adult English speakers. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. (in press).

Berry, L. (1998). Alignment and Adjacency in Optimality Theory: Evidence from Walpiri and Arrernte. Sydney, NSW: University of Sydney.

Google Scholar

Breen, G., and Pensalfini, R. (2001). A language with no syllable onsets. Ling. Inq. 30, 1–25. doi: 10.1162/002438999553940

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brentari, D. (1993). Establishing a sonority hierarchy in American Sign Language: the use of simultaneous structure in phonology. Phonology 10, 281–306. doi: 10.1017/S0952675700000063

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brentari, D., Coppola, M., Mazzoni, L., and Goldin-Meadow, S. (2012). When does a system become phonological? Handshape production in gestures, signers and homesigners. Nat. Lang. Ling. Theor. 30, 1–31. doi: 10.1007/s11049-011-9145-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Buchwald, A. (2009). Minimizing and optimizing structure in phonology: evidence from aphasia. Lingua 119, 1380–1395. doi: 10.1016/j.lingua.2007.11.015

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Buchwald, A. B., Rapp, B., and Stone, M. (2007). Insertion of discrete phonological units: an articulatory and acoustic investigation of aphasic speech. Lang. Cogn. Process 22, 910–948. doi: 10.1080/01690960701273532

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Carey, S. (2009). The Origin of Concepts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Carey, S., and Spelke, E. (1996). Science and core knowledge. Philos. Sci. 63, 515–533. doi: 10.1086/289971

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Carey, S., and Xu, F. (2001). Infants’ knowledge of objects: beyond object files and object tracking. Cognition 80, 179–213. doi: 10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00154-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chomsky, N. (2014). Science, Mind, and Limits of Understanding. The Vatican: The Science and Faith Foundation (STOQ).

Clements, G. N. (1990). “The role of the sonority cycle in core syllabification,” in Papers in Laboratory Phonology I: Between the Grammar and Physics of Speech, eds J. Kingston and M. Beckman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 282–333.

Google Scholar

Cohen-Goldberg, A. M., Cholin, J., Miozzo, M., and Rapp, B. (2013). The interface between morphology and phonology: exploring a morpho-phonological deficit in spoken production. Cognition 127, 270–286. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.01.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coppola, M., and Brentari, D. (2014). From iconic handshapes to grammatical contrasts: Longitudinal evidence from a child homesigner. Front. Psychol. 5:830. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00830

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Daland, R., Hayes, B., Garellek, M., White, J., Davis, A., and Norrmann, I. (2011). Explaining sonority projection effects. Phonology 28, 197–234. doi: 10.1017/S0952675711000145

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Davidson, L., and Shaw, J. A. (2012). Sources of illusion in consonant cluster perception. J. Phon. 40, 234–248. doi: 10.1016/j.wocn.2011.11.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

de Hevia, M. D., Izard, V., Coubart, A., Spelke, E. S., and Streri, A. (2014). Representations of space, time, and number in neonates. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 111, 4809–4813. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1323628111

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

de Lacy, P. (2004). Markedness conflation in optimality theory. Phonology 21, 145–188. doi: 10.1017/S0952675704000193

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

DeFrancis, J. (1989). Visible Speech: The Diverse Oneness of Writing Systems. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press.

Google Scholar

Eimas, P. D., Siqueland, E. R., Jusczyk, P., and Vigorito, J. (1971). Speech perception in infants. Science 171, 303–306. doi: 10.1126/science.171.3968.303

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Embick, D., and Poeppel, D. (2015). Towards a computational(ist) neurobiology of language: correlational, integrated, and explanatory neurolinguistics. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 30, 357–366. doi: 10.1080/23273798.2014.980750

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Everett, D. L. (2016a). Dark Matter of the Mind: The Culturally Articulated Unconscious. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Everett, D. L. (2016b). An evaluation of universal grammar and the phonological mind. Front. Psychol. 7:15. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00015

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fadiga, L., Craighero, L., Buccino, G., and Rizzolatti, G. (2002). Speech listening specifically modulates the excitability of tongue muscles: a TMS study. Eur. J. Nuerosci. 15, 399–402. doi: 10.1046/j.0953-816x.2001.01874.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Feigenson, L., Carey, S., and Hauser, M. (2002). The representations underlying infants’ choice of more: object files versus analog magnitudes. Psychol. Sci. 13, 150–156. doi: 10.1111/1467-9280.00427

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Flombaum, J. I., Junge, J. A., and Hauser, M. D. (2005). Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta) spontaneously compute addition operations over large numbers. Cognition 97, 315–325. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2004.09.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fodor, J., and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. Cognition 28, 3–71. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gervain, J., Berent, I., and Werker, J. (2012). Binding at birth: newborns detect identity relations and sequential position in speech. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 24, 564–574. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_00157

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gómez, D. M., Berent, I., Benavides-Varela, S., Bion, R. A. H., Cattarossi, L., Nespor, M., et al. (2014). Language universals at birth. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 111, 5837–5341. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1318261111

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gouskova, M. (2001). Falling sonority onsets, loanwords, and syllable contact. CLS 37, 175–185.

Google Scholar

Greenberg, J. H. (1950). The patterning of morphemes in semitic. Word 6, 162–181.

Google Scholar

Greenberg, J., H. (1978). “Some generalizations concerning initial and final consonant clusters,” in Universals of Human Language, Vol. 2, eds J. H. Greenberg, C. A. Ferguson, and E. A. Moravcsik (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press), 243–279.

Google Scholar

Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., and Bloom, P. (2007). Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature 450, 557–559. doi: 10.1038/nature06288

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., and Bloom, P. (2010). Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. Dev. Sci. 13, 923–929. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2010.00951.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hermer, L., and Spelke, E. S. (1994). A geometric process for spatial reorientation in young children. Nature 370, 57–59. doi: 10.1038/370057a0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hooper, J. B. (1976). An Introduction to Natural Generative Phonology. New York, NY: Academic Press.

Google Scholar

Izard, V., Sann, C., Spelke, E. S., and Streri, A. (2009). Newborn infants perceive abstract numbers. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106, 10382–10385. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0812142106

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kiparsky, P. (1979). Metrical structure assignment is cyclic. Ling. Inq. 10, 421–442.

Google Scholar

Kisilevsky, B. S., Hains, S. M. J., Brown, C. A., Lee, C. T., Cowperthwaite, B., Stutzman, S. S., et al. (2009). Fetal sensitivity to properties of maternal speech and language. Infant Behav. Dev. 32, 59–71. doi: 10.1016/j.infbeh.2008.10.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lennertz, T., and Berent, I. (2015). On the sonority levels of fricatives and stops. Men. Lex. 10, 88–132. doi: 10.1075/ml.10.1.04len

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leslie, A. M. (2005). Developmental parallels in understanding minds and bodies. Trends Cogn. Sci. 9, 459–462. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.08.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Liu, F., van Duijn, K., Vingerling, J. R., Hofman, A., Uitterlinden, A. G., Janssens, A. C. J. W., et al. (2009). Eye color and the prediction of complex phenotypes from genotypes. Curr. Biol. 19, R192–R193. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2009.01.027

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Marcus, G. F., Vijayan, S., Bandi Rao, S., and Vishton, P. M. (1999). Rule learning by seven-month-old infants. Science 283, 77–80. doi: 10.1126/science.283.5398.77

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McCarthy, J. J. (1994). “The phonetics and phonology of Semitic pharyngeals,” in Papers in Laboratory Phonology III, ed. P. Keating (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 191–283.

Google Scholar

McCarthy, J. J., and Prince, A. (1994). The emergence of the unmarked: optimality in prosodic morphology. Paper Presented at the Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society, Amherst, MA.

Google Scholar

McCarthy, J. J., and Prince, A. (1995). “Prosodic morphology,” in Phonological Theory, ed. J. A. Goldsmith (Oxford: Basil Blackwell), 318–366.

Google Scholar

Miozzo, M., and Buchwald, A. (2013). On the nature of sonority in spoken word production: evidence from neuropsychology. Cognition 128, 287–301. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.04.006

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ohala, J. J. (1990). Alternatives to the sonority hierarchy for explaining segmental sequential constraints. Papers Regional Meetings 2, 319–338.

Parker, S. (2002). Quantifying the Sonority Hierarchy. doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, MA.

Google Scholar

Parker, S. (2008). Sound level protrusions as physical correlates of sonority. J. Phon. 36, 55–90. doi: 10.1016/j.wocn.2007.09.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parker, S. (2012). The Sonority Controversy. Berlin: de Gruyter Mouton.

Google Scholar

Perfetti, C. (1985). Reading Ability. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Perlmutter, D. M. (1992). Sonority and syllable structure in american sign language. Ling. Inq. 23, 407–442.

Google Scholar

Prince, A., and Smolensky, P. (1993/2004). Optimality Theory: Constraint Interaction in Generative Grammar. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

Google Scholar

Pulvermüller, F., Huss, M., Kherif, F., Moscoso del Prado Martin, F., Hauk, O., and Shtyrov, Y. (2006). Motor cortex maps articulatory features of speech sounds. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 7865–7870. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0509989103

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Redford, M. A. (2008). Production constraints on learning novel onset phonotactics. Cognition 107, 785–816. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2007.11.014

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ridley, M. (2003). Nature via Nurture : Genes, Experience, and What Makes us Human, 1 Edn. New York, NY: Harper Collins.

Google Scholar

Samuels, R. (2004). Innateness in cognitive science. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 136–141. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sandler, W. (1993). A sonority cycle in American sign language. Phonology 10, 242–279. doi: 10.1017/S0952675700000051

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sandler, W., Aronoff, M., Meir, I., and Padden, C. (2011). The gradual emergence of phonological form in a new language. Nat. Lang. Ling. Theor. 29, 505–543. doi: 10.1007/s11049-011-9128-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sarnat, H. B., Resch, L., Flores-Sarnat, L., and Yu, W. (2014). Precocious synapses in 13.5-week fetal holoprosencephalic cortex and cyclopean retina. Brain Dev. 36, 463–471. doi: 10.1016/j.braindev.2014.01.008

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Saussure, F. D. (1915/1959). Course in General Linguistics. New York, NY: Philosophical Library.

Google Scholar

Selkirk, E. O. (1982). “The syllable,” in The Structure of Phonological Representations, eds H. Van der Hulst and N. Smith (Dordrecht: Foris Publications), 337–383.

Google Scholar

Selkirk, E. O. (1984). “On the major class features and syllable theory,” in Language Sound Structure: Studies in Phonology Presented to Morris Halle by his Teacher and Students, eds M. Aronoff and R. T. Oerhle (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 107–136.

Google Scholar

Smolensky, P. (2006). “Optimality in phonology II: harmonic completeness, local constraint conjunction, and feature domain markedness,” in The Harmonic Mind: From Neural Computation to Optimality-Theoretic Grammar: Linguistic and Philosophical Implications, Vol. 2, eds P. Smolensky and G. Legendre (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 27–160.

Google Scholar

Spelke, E. (1994). Initial knowledge: six suggestions. Cognition 50, 431–445. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(94)90039-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spelke, E. S. (2000). Core knowledge. Am. Psychol. 55, 1233–1243.

Google Scholar

Spelke, E. S., and Kinzler, K. D. (2007). Core knowledge. Dev. Sci. 10, 89–96. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2007.00569.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Steriade, D. (1982). Greek Prosodies and the Nature of Syllabification; Ph.D. dissertation. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge.

Google Scholar

Tamasi, K., and Berent, I. (2015). Sensitivity to phonological universals: the case of fricatives and stops. J. Psychol. Res. 44, 359–381.

Google Scholar

Topintzi, N., and Nevins, A. (2014). “Moraic onsets and cross-anchoring in arrernte,” in Proceedings of the 22nd Manchester Phonology Meeting. Manchester.

Google Scholar

Uller, C., Hauser, M., and Carey, S. (2001). Spontaneous representation of number in cotton-top tamarins (Saguinus oedipus). J. Comp. Psychol. 115, 248–257. doi: 10.1037/0735-7036.115.3.248

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van Orden, G. C., Pennington, B. F., and Stone, G. O. (1990). Word identification in reading and the promise of subsymbolic psycholinguistics. Psychol. Rev. 97, 488–522. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.97.4.488

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vennemann, T. (1972). On the theory of syllable phonology. Ling. Ber. 18, 1–18.

Google Scholar

Werker, J. F., and Tees, R. C. (1984). Cross-language speech perception: evidence for perceptual reorganization during the first year of life. Infant Behav. Dev. 7, 49–63. doi: 10.1016/S0163-6383(84)80022-3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Williams, J. T., and Newman, S. D. (2016). Impacts of visual sonority and handshape markedness on second language learning of american sign language. J. Deaf Stud. Deaf Edu. 21, 171–186. doi: 10.1093/deafed/env055

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, C., Davidson, L., and Martin, S. (2014). Effects of acoustic–phonetic detail on cross-language speech production. J. Mem. Lang. 77, 1–24. doi: 10.1016/j.jml.2014.08.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wynn, K., Bloom, P., and Chiang, W.-C. (2002). Enumeration of collective entities by 5-month-old infants. Cognition 83, B55–B62. doi: 10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00008-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zec, D. (2007). “The syllable,” in The Cambridge Handbook of Phonology, ed. P. de Lacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 161–194.

Google Scholar

Zhao, X. (2015). Exploring Universal Phonological Preferences: Beyond Articulation. Boston, MA: Northeastern University.

Google Scholar

Zhao, X., and Berent, I. (2015). Universal restrictions on syllable structure: evidence from mandarin chinese. J. Psycholinguist. Res. doi: 10.1007/s10936-015-9375-1 [Epub ahead of print].

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: phonology, universal grammar, core knoweldge, innateness, sonority

Citation: Berent I (2016) Commentary: “An Evaluation of Universal Grammar and the Phonological Mind”—UG Is Still a Viable Hypothesis. Front. Psychol. 7:1029. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01029

Received: 04 February 2016; Accepted: 23 June 2016;
Published: 14 July 2016.

Edited by:

Itziar Laka, University of the Basque Country, Spain

Reviewed by:

Ariel M. Cohen-Goldberg, Tufts University, USA
Marc Van Oostendorp, Meertens Instituut, Netherlands

Copyright © 2016 Berent. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Iris Berent, i.berent@neu.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.