Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Genet., 20 July 2012
Sec. Genetics of Aging

What is Aging?

  • 1 Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of California, Irvine, CA, USA
  • 2 Department of Biomedical Sciences, Institute of Population Genetics, Vetmeduni Vienna, Vienna, Austria
  • 3 Joint School of Nanoscience and Nanoengineering, North Carolina A&T State University, UNC Greensboro, Greensboro, NC, USA
  • 4 Department of Biology, La Sierra University, Riverside, CA, USA
  • 5 Department of Biology, Pomona College, Claremont, CA, USA
  • 6 Centro de Biologia Ambiental, Departamento de Biologia Animal, Faculdade de Ciencias da Universidade de Lisboa, Campo Grande, Lisboa, Portugal
  • 7 Central Arkansas Veterans Healthcare System, Department of Geriatrics and Biochemistry/Molecular Biology, University of Arkansas for Medical Sciences, Little Rock, AR, USA

In 1991, the book Evolutionary Biology of Aging offered the following definition of aging: a persistent decline in the age-specific fitness components of an organism due to internal physiological deterioration (Rose, 1991). This definition has since been used by others a number of times. However, it was only a modest generalization of a definition proffered by Alex Comfort over three editions (1956–1979) of his key book The Biology of Senescence (Comfort, 1979): “a progressive increase throughout life, or after a given stadium, in the likelihood that a given individual will die, during the next succeeding unit of time, from randomly distributed causes.” The 1991 definition chiefly added reproductive fitness components to Comfort’s definition, while adding the qualifiers that the fitness-component decline should be persistent and should be “due to internal physiological deterioration,” where the latter phrase was meant fairly broadly. Thus increases in mortality with age due to chronic infections such as HIV/AIDS were excluded by the 1991 definition.

Yet a mere definition does not necessarily tell a scientist what causally underlies the phenomenon that is so defined. The latter issue is much broader, implicitly raising fundamental scientific questions regarding mechanisms. As a simple but related example, the term adaptation can be defined as an attribute that enhances the net reproduction of members of a particular population or species, and yet many deeper issues are invoked by a question like, “What is adaptation?” A creationist, for example, could view adaptation as an attribute that is so defined, yet further assume that all such adaptations are specifically bequeathed to organisms by an omnipotent creator. By contrast, an evolutionary biologist would instead assume that such adaptations are necessarily products of natural selection, acting directly or indirectly.

Before 1992, almost every scientist who thought about aging assumed that it progressed without remit to the point of death. Evolutionary biologists further thought that this inexorable deterioration was brought about by the progressive decline in Hamilton’s forces of natural selection (Hamilton, 1966; Rose et al., 2007). With respect to the underlying physiological machinery of aging, the only difference between most evolutionists and most gerontologists at that time was that evolutionists overwhelmingly expected that there were likely to be many physiological mechanisms of deterioration, rather than a few (Williams, 1957; Rose, 1991). Thus the aforementioned 1991 book accommodated commonly inferred physiological mechanisms of aging within an overarching evolutionary framework, thus delineating an “evolutionary biology of aging” that subsumed conventional gerontological thinking, rejecting only those parts that were inconsistent with evolutionary theory.

This synthesis of evolutionary biology and gerontology survived for only 1 year before being undermined by two 1992 papers, Curtsinger et al. (1992) and Carey et al. (1992), in which demographic aging was shown to subside in late-life among cohorts of Drosophila and the medfly. Some initial attempts to accommodate their results focused on possible density artifacts (Nusbaum et al., 1993), but a substantive series of experiments from the Curtsinger lab (Khazaeli et al., 1995, 1998a,b) demolished such quibbling. By 1995, it was clear that the cessation of aging was a genuine phenomenon rather than an experimental artifact.

Yet another possibility remained, one that had been discussed in 1939 by Greenwood and Irwin (1939) in their article showing that human aging stopped demographically: lifelong heterogeneity. This is a concept that has been mathematically developed, particularly by Vaupel (Vaupel et al., 1979; Vaupel, 1988), but it is fairly easy to convey as a verbal argument. If a cohort consists of sub-cohorts that differ radically in their lifelong robustness, then the less robust will be eliminated early, leaving only the much more robust individuals. If these surviving sub-cohorts are robust enough, demographic aging should greatly slow at very late ages.

Many have looked for evidence of such an association between lifelong robustness and the cessation of aging (Khazaeli et al., 1998a,b; Drapeau et al., 2000; Mueller et al., 2003; Rauser et al., 2005). It is possible to produce such a mortality-rate flattening by artificially constructing cohorts out of very different sub-cohorts (Brooks et al., 1994), but no one has yet found enough naturally occurring lifelong heterogeneity to generate demographic plateaus in age-specific mortality or fecundity (reviewed in Shahrestani et al., 2009; Mueller et al., 2011). Indeed, there are good evolutionary genetic reasons to expect that such lifelong heterogeneity will rarely arise: natural selection will oppose the maintenance of such heterogeneity, whether it is due to genetic polymorphism or extreme non-genetic plasticity (Mueller et al., 2011, Chapter 7). Natural selection instead favors the maintenance of genetic variation affecting fitness-components when that genetic variation has opposed effects at different ages, in other words antagonistic pleiotropy, not lifelong effects that are consistent in direction (Rose, 1985; Mueller et al., 2011).

Thus it appears that the cessation of aging occurs at the individual level, and is not just an artifact of population structure. Yet this is clearly paradoxical, if we think of the machinery of aging in terms of such physiological processes as steadily cumulative damage. If it is supposed that some process of cumulative damage or disharmony is supposed to underlie aging, why should that process abruptly stop at the very point, late in adult life, when it has greatly reduced the ability of the surviving individuals to sustain life and reproduction?

Mueller, Rauser, and Rose instead developed very different models for the evolution of late-life plateaus in mortality and fecundity (Mueller and Rose, 1996; Mueller et al., 2011), using the eventual plateaus in Hamilton’s forces of natural selection as their core explanatory principle for mortality and fecundity plateaus late in adult life. These formal mathematical models, founded in evolutionary genetics, show that it is perfectly reasonable for natural selection to produce late-life plateaus in life-history characters, especially with finite population sizes, once the forces of natural selection have fallen to very low values. Of greater significance for strong-inference science, they further demonstrated that experimental evolution can tune the timing of the cessation of Drosophila aging in conformity with these theoretical results (Rose et al., 2002; Rauser et al., 2006). Indeed, the discovery that aging stops turns out to be a powerful corroboration of Hamilton’s original results for the forces of natural selection (Hamilton, 1966; Mueller et al., 2011), all the more dramatic because it was counterintuitive and hence unexpected.

These results call for some fundamental re-thinking of what aging is. Twenty years ago, evolutionary biologists imagined that once Hamilton’s forces of natural selection reached zero, death should quickly follow due to the absence of natural selection opposing the effects of cumulative damage and/or regulatory disharmony. Now at least some have a very different vision (Mueller et al., 2011). As Hamilton’s forces of natural selection decline during the first part of adulthood, we might say that age-specific elements of adaptation are de-tuned. This de-tuning in turn could be said to generate the demographic phenomena of aging, as well as the myriad physiological dysfunctions that we know as the seemingly, but actually secondary, mechanistic foundations of aging. In species with sufficiently severe antagonistic pleiotropy between reproduction and adult survival, such as Pacific salmon, soybean, and mayflies, all members of a cohort may die without either a well-defined period of aging or late life, in the absence of human intervention. But under sufficiently benign environmental conditions, individuals from species as disparate as humans and fruit flies can survive a protracted aging period and reach a subsequent late-life respite in which fitness-component deterioration stops, a phase permitted by the complete attenuation of the forces of natural selection relative to the effects of genetic drift.

The above results suggest that aging is not inevitably a cumulative and unremitting process of deterioration. Instead, aging might be best conceived as a facet of adaptation, specifically its de-tuning during the first part of adulthood. This de-tuning is due to the steady declines in the forces of natural selection that occur after the start of adulthood in most populations. Once those declines stop, aging eventually ceases, and adaptation stabilizes albeit at a low level. There is little sign of a physiological “momentum” that necessarily advances aging until every member of a cohort has died; nor is there any a priori requirement for such constancy, despite the seductive analogy to Newtonian physics. An important corollary is that many of the standard biological intuitions about aging, particularly those that associate it with the Second Law of Thermodynamics, are not generally valid. Some functional declines of physiological characters continue into late-life, and some even accelerate, whereas other functional declines come to a halt (Shahrestani et al., 2012). There is thus no scientific justification for assuming that each and every type of physiological deterioration that has been associated with aging must continue without remit throughout late adult life.

This realization leads to another fundamental change in our thinking about “the process of aging”: it is not actually a physiological process, in and of itself. Although it certainly involves physiological changes, the physiology of aging is molded and constrained according to the dictates of natural selection shaping adaptation. Some of the genetic foundations of adaptation serve to sustain survival and reproduction later in life, presumably because of age-independent benefits (Charlesworth, 2001). Other features of adaptation are apparently subject to age-specific and pleiotropic genetic effects which undermine age-specific mortality and fecundity, together with their underlying physiology, during middle adulthood (Rose, 1991; Rose et al., 2002; Mueller et al., 2011). In extreme cases of trade-offs between survival and reproduction, continued adult survival may be wholly sacrificed by natural selection, resulting in semelparous, univoltine, or annual life cycles (Rose, 1991). All these possibilities for patterns of aging are permitted by evolution.

The evolutionary biology of aging proposed in 1991 (Rose, 1991) provided some warrant for allowing gerontologists to conduct their research largely without evolutionary considerations. The falling forces of natural selection were supposed to ensure the cumulative and unremitting physiological deterioration commonly assumed by gerontologists. But now neither that evolutionary rationale nor that type of mechanistic thinking seem warranted, given what we know of the cessation of aging. At its very foundations, aging is a multifaceted phenomenon that is a derivative feature of the evolutionary biology of adaptation, not a single physiological process, even though adaptations generally involve physiology.

As such, aging is best studied in light of the methodological strictures and theoretical scaffolding supplied by evolutionary biology. Some of those elements were sketched in 1991 (Rose, 1991), but the analysis offered then was far too simplistic. We now know that aging is much more complex than was understood then, both genomically (Rose and Burke, 2011) and demographically (Mueller et al., 2011), and it is inseparable from adaptation itself (Rose, 2009). This makes it a hazardous proposition to study aging without significant attention to evolutionary genetics. An evolutionary-genetic perspective on aging raises several points of concern, including the difficulty of studying aging under conditions in which adaptation has been undermined or distorted, such as breeding regimes that create inbreeding depression, highly artificial genotype-by-environment interactions, and obscure evolutionary history (Rose et al., 2011). As aging is neither more nor less than the deterioration of adaptation with adult age, obscuring the features of adaptation by performing experiments with laboratory cohorts of an abnormally inbred and/or mutated strain with a poorly documented history of laboratory culture has created and will perpetuate significant difficulties of interpretation.

This vision of what underlies aging may be off-putting for some, given its theoretical complexities and difficulties for experimental design. No doubt many physicists felt the same way about the destruction of the elegant late nineteenth Century version of Newtonian mechanics by the advent of relativistic and quantum mechanics, in the period from 1905 to 1945. But paradigm transitions in science are generally like that, requiring that we abandon comfortable theories in favor of those that are significantly less wrong.

The genetics of aging cannot go on as it did before 1992. We need not jettison every lesson gleaned from past research, whether evolutionary or mechanistic, though conclusions reached under the quondam paradigm now require re-examination within our current, broader understanding. We will be able to salvage those parts that can be reintegrated within a scientific framework for the evolutionary genetics of aging, developed in light of its fundamental nature: de-tuned adaptation during the first part of adulthood. But a new evolutionary genetics of aging must now be built.

References

Brooks, A., Lithgow, G. J., and Johnson, T. E. (1994). Mortality-rates in a genetically heterogeneous population of Caenorhabditis elegans. Science 263, 668–671.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Carey, J. R., Liedo, P., Orozco, D., and Vaupel, J. W. (1992). Slowing of mortality rates at older ages in large medfly cohorts. Science 258, 457–461.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Charlesworth, B. (2001). Patterns of age-specific means and genetic variances of mortality rates predicted by the mutation-accumulation theory of ageing. J. Theor. Biol. 210, 47–65.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Comfort, A. (1979). The Biology of Senescence, 3rd Edn. Edinburgh and London: Churchill Livingstone.

Curtsinger, J. W., Fukui, H. H., Townsend, D. R., and Vaupel, J. W. (1992). Demography of genotypes: failure of the limited life span paradigm in Drosophila melanogaster. Science 258, 461–463.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Drapeau, M. D., Gass, E. K., Simison, M. D., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (2000). Testing the heterogeneity theory of late-life mortality plateaus by using cohorts of Drosophila melanogaster. Exp. Gerontol. 35, 71–84.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Greenwood, M., and Irwin, J. O. (1939). Biostatistics of senility. Hum. Biol. 11, 1–23.

Hamilton, W. D. (1966). The moulding of senescence by natural selection. J. Theor. Biol. 12, 12–45.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Khazaeli, A. A., Xiu, L., and Curtsinger, J. W. (1995). Effect of adult cohort density on age-specific mortality in Drosophila melanogaster. J. Gerontol. A 50, 262–269.

CrossRef Full Text

Khazaeli, A. A., Xiu, L., and Curtsinger, J. W. (1998a). Effect of density on age-specific mortality in Drosophila: a density supplementation experiment. Genetica 98, 21–31.

CrossRef Full Text

Khazaeli, A. A., Pletcher, S. D., and Curtsinger, J. W. (1998b). The fractionation experiment: reducing heterogeneity to investigate age-specific mortality in Drosophila. Mech. Ageing Dev. 105, 301–317.

CrossRef Full Text

Mueller, L. D., Drapeau, M. D., Adams, C. S., Hammerle, C. W., Doyal, K. M., Jazayeri, A. J., Ly, T., Beguwala, S. A., Mamidi, A. R., and Rose, M. R. (2003). Statistical tests of demographic heterogeneity theories. Exp. Gerontol. 38, 373–386.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mueller, L. D., Rauser, C. L., and Rose, M. R. (2011). Does Aging Stop? New York: Oxford University Press.

Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (1996). Evolutionary theory predicts late-life mortality plateaus. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 93, 15249–15253.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Nusbaum, T. J., Graves, J. L., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (1993). Letter to the editor. Science 260, 1567.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rauser, C. L., Abdel-Aal, Y., Shieh, J. A., Suen, C. W., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (2005). Lifelong heterogeneity infecundity is insufficient to explain late-life fecundity plateaus in Drosophila melanogaster. Exp. Gerontol. 40, 660–670.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rauser, C. L., Tierney, J. J., Gunion, S. M., Covarrubias, G. M., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (2006). Evolution of late-life fecundity in Drosophila melanogaster. J. Evol. Biol. 19, 289–301.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rose, M. R. (1985). Life-history evolution with antagonistic pleiotropy and overlapping generations. Theor. Pop. Biol. 28, 342–358.

CrossRef Full Text

Rose, M. R. (1991). Evolutionary Biology of Aging. New York: Oxford University Press.

Rose, M. R. (2009). Adaptation, aging, and genomic information. Aging 1, 444–450.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Rose, M. R., and Burke, M. K. (2011). Genomic Croesus: experimental evolutionary genetics of aging. Exp. Gerontol. 46, 397–403.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rose, M. R., Drapeau, M. D., Yazdi, P. G., Shah, K. H., Moise, D. B., Thakar, R. R., Rauser, C. L., and Mueller, L. D. (2002). Evolution of late-life mortality in Drosophila melanogaster. Evolution 56, 1982–1991.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rose, M. R., Mueller, L. D., and Burke, M. K. (2011). New experiments for an undivided genetics. Genetics 188, 1–10.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rose, M. R., Rauser, C. L., Benford, G., Matos, M., and Mueller, L. D. (2007). Hamilton’s forces of natural selection after forty years. Evolution 61, 1265–1276.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Shahrestani, P., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (2009). Does aging stop? Curr. Aging Sci. 2, 3–11.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Shahrestani, P., Quach, J., Mueller, L. D., and Rose, M. R. (2012). Paradoxical physiological transitions from aging to late life in Drosophila. Rejuvenation Res. 15, 49–58.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Vaupel, J. W. (1988). Inherited frailty and longevity. Demography 25, 277–287.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Vaupel, J. W., Manton, K. G., and Stallard, E. (1979). The impact of heterogeneity in individual frailty on the dynamics of mortality. Demography 16, 439–454.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Williams, G. C. (1957). Pleiotropy, natural selection, and the evolution of senescence. Evolution 11, 398–411.

CrossRef Full Text

Citation: Rose MR, Flatt T, Graves JL, Greer LF, Martínez DE, Matos M, Mueller LD, Shmookler Reis RJ and Shahrestani P (2012) What is aging? Front. Gene. 3:134. doi: 10.3389/fgene.2012.00134

Received: 02 July 2012; Accepted: 03 July 2012;
Published online: 20 July 2012.

Edited by:

John Tower, University of Southern California, USA

Reviewed by:

John Tower, University of Southern California, USA

Copyright: © 2012 Rose, Flatt, Graves, Greer, Martínez, Matos, Mueller, Shmookler Reis and Shahrestani. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in other forums, provided the original authors and source are credited and subject to any copyright notices concerning any third-party graphics etc.

*Correspondence: mrrose@uci.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.