Skip to main content

MINI REVIEW article

Front. Hum. Neurosci., 14 July 2014
Sec. Cognitive Neuroscience
Volume 8 - 2014 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00505

When mirroring is both simple and “smart”: how mimicry can be embodied, adaptive, and non-representational

  • 1Department of Psychology, University of California - San Diego, La Jolla, CA, USA
  • 2Department of Cognitive Science, University of California - San Diego, La Jolla, CA, USA
  • 3Faculty of Psychology, University of Social Sciences and Humanities, Warsaw, Poland

The concept of mirroring has become rather ubiquitous. One of the most fundamental empirical and theoretical debates within research on mirroring concerns the role of mental representations: while some models argue that higher-order representational mechanisms underpin most cases of mirroring, other models argue that they only moderate a primarily non-representational process. As such, even though research on mirroring—along with its neural substrates, including the putative mirror neuron system—has grown tremendously, so too has confusion about what it actually means to “mirror”. Using recent research on spontaneous imitation, we argue that flexible mirroring effects can be fully embodied and dynamic—even in the absence of higher-order mental representations. We propose that mirroring can simply reflect an adaptive integration and utilization of cues obtained from the brain, body, and environment, which is especially evident within the social context. Such a view offers reconciliation among both representational and non-representational frameworks in cognitive neuroscience, which will facilitate revised interpretations of modern (and seemingly divergent) findings on when and how these embodied mirroring responses are employed.

Introduction

There is now great interest in the idea of an embodied mind. Much evidence suggests that thought and action are grounded in perceptual and sensorimotor states, while being shaped by the environment in which they take place (e.g., Niedenthal et al., 2005). But how does this grounding and shaping occur, what are the regulatory mechanisms, and when (if ever) are higher-order representations necessary? In the current article, we explore these questions in the context of debates about the role of mirroring in social cognition.

One dominant idea guiding embodiment research on social cognition is that individuals understand others by replicating their states, using one’s own somatosensory resources. On the neural level, this function is often assigned to the putative mirror neuron system (MNS), which “re-creates” the observed action in the perceiver (Blakemore and Decety, 2001; Gallese, 2003a; Rizzolatti and Craighero, 2004). Several mirroring accounts appeal to higher-order representational processes (e.g., Goldman and Sripada, 2005), and while definitions of “mental representations” certainly do vary, those models usually view them as outcomes of propositional encoding of incoming sensory information into language-like mental symbols, which can then be internally manipulated, and finally back-translated into motoric processes that lead to action (Gallese, 2003a,b). We will return to these definitional issues later.

Critically, what makes the “mirroring” idea and related phenomena appealing is the possibility that they reveal a non-representational relation to others (Gallagher, 2007; Hutto, 2007; Sinigaglia, 2009). With the following, we illustrate and expand on this general point, using recent literature on spontaneous imitation (or the reflexive mimicry of another’s actions or behaviors). Such imitation—of gestures, finger movements, facial expressions, etc.—plays a role in empathy, affiliation, and rapport (Chartrand and van Baaren, 2009). Importantly, this imitation can sometimes be direct (e.g., smile-to-a-smile, index-finger to index-finger, etc.), possibly reflecting operation of low-level ideomotor processes (Brass et al., 2000; Gallese, 2003a; Catmur et al., 2009).

Note, however, that non-representational accounts of mirroring face a basic problem, when imitation is indirect: as we will elaborate on shortly, perceivers do indeed faithfully “mirror” or replicate the observed state—but only sometimes. In fact, individuals often engage in adaptable, context-sensitive responding, whereby this direct perceiver-observer correspondence goes beyond a mere reflection of what is observed. This flexibility is often highlighted by critics of the non-representational accounts to embodiment, as presumably necessitating mediation by higher-order representations. Indeed, some recent theories of imitation explicitly suggest that such contextual modification reveals the mediating role of higher-order constructs, such as sophisticated appraisals, meaning-construction, and even theory-of-mind (Wang and Hamilton, 2012; Hess and Fischer, 2013).

Consequently, to address the problem of indirect imitation, any sophisticated non-representational account needs to explain how perceivers’ responses to the observed action reflect dynamic integration of perception-action links, bodily states, and social-environmental cues (Chemero, 2009). Such accounts should explain how context-dependent shaping of embodiment can not only occur quickly, implicitly, and with little conscious awareness, but also how this can manifest even in animals (de Waal and Ferrari, 2010; Barrett, 2011) and “embodied” robots (Wilson and Golonka, 2013), which have limited capacities for higher-order mental representations. If successful, this suggests an exciting, novel alternative perspective on the flexibility of mirroring, where higher-order representations are not necessary.

Our view assumes that flexible mirroring effects can be fully embodied, dynamic, and adaptive—even in the absence of higher-order mental representations. We propose that spontaneous mirroring can be “smart”, in the sense that the process can simply and efficiently utilize integrative environmental cues. To demonstrate this, we offer a snapshot of the recent findings on spontaneous imitation, situated within this debate about the mediating role of higher-order mental representations.

Arguments for Representational Models

Many representational arguments for mirroring arose during initial interpretational debates regarding neurons in ventral premotor cortex that discharge both during action-performance and action-observation (originally, in area F5 of the rhesus macaque; Rizzolatti and Craighero, 2004). The popular early “adaptationist” frameworks argue that the MNS was evolutionarily selected to subserve action-understanding and promote social learning (Iacoboni, 2009). Importantly, different models within this broad domain vary in their explanation of the underlying mechanisms for how mirroring is instantiated and recruited. For instance, some argue that the observer has a common cognitive representational format for perception and action (i.e., active intermodal matching models; Preston and De Waal, 2002; Meltzoff and Decety, 2003), that mirroring is dependent on internal re-creations of others’ states in order to facilitate understanding and co-regulation (i.e., simulationist and embodiment frameworks; Goldman and Sripada, 2005; Semin and Cacioppo, 2009), or that imitation is fundamentally shaped by higher-level meaning-constructions (i.e., social and emotional frameworks; Hamilton, 2013; Hess and Fischer, 2013; Reed and McIntosh, 2013). Critically though, while these models differ in how they explain the function of the MNS (and the resultant tendencies toward mirroring), all agree that the cognitive and neural resources that allow such mirroring to occur are substantially dependent on higher-order representations, which then act to advance action-learning, recognition, and understanding.

Arguably some of the strongest pro-representational arguments came from the interpretation of studies showing that our imitative capacities are “smart”—that is, mirroring responses dynamically adapt to environmental cues, for both motor and facial behaviors. As examples, motor imitation (e.g., finger-lifting, hand-opening and closing, etc.) is modulated by prosocial attitudes (Leighton et al., 2010b), incidental similarity (Guéguen and Martin, 2009), affiliative drive (Lakin and Chartrand, 2003), and even eye contact (Wang et al., 2011). Interestingly, emotional imitation exhibits an even greater bit of flexibility: for example, spontaneous facial mimicry of emotional expressions (i.e., smile-to-a-smile, frown-to-a-frown, etc.) can change dramatically according to social factors, like outgroup membership (Bourgeois and Hess, 2008), negative attitudes (Likowski et al., 2008), competition (Weyers et al., 2009), and social power (Carr et al., 2014). Since many of these studies use sensitive psychophysiological techniques (e.g., electromyography [EMG] to gauge motor activity over different facial muscles; e.g., Carr et al., 2014) and neuroscientific methods (e.g., single-unit recordings in humans; Mukamel et al., 2010; see Figures 1C,D), these findings suggest that even at the lowest level, facial mimicry is sensitive to contextual cues, basic appraisals, and rudimentary goal processes (Hess and Fischer, 2013). Crucially, the representational models posit that higher-order constructs are required for such contextual modifications to occur.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Human neural responses when mirroring and responding to others. Panels A and B (figure and caption are reprinted from Van Overwalle and Baetens (2009) with permission from Elsevier) depict the regions of interest involved in the mirror and mentalizing system placed in an x–y–z Talairach atlas. Their centers are indicated by a dot and include pSTS (±50 −55 10), TPJ (±50 −55 25), aIPS (±40 −40 45), PMC (±40 5 40) and mPFC (0 50 20). The PC (with center 0 −60 40) is not shown. The regions are drawn based on the recent literature and, in particular, on Keysers and Gazzola (2006; panel A) for the mirror system and on Van Overwalle (2009; panel B) for the mentalizing system. Panels C and D (figure and caption are reprinted from Mukamel et al. (2010) with permission from Elsevier) show neural responses of two cells during all experimental conditions and tasks, which depicts an action observation/execution matching multiunit in left SMA for the two grips (precision and whole-hand; panel C) and an action observation/execution matching single unit in right entorhinal cortex for two facial gestures (smile and frown; panel D). Rasters (top) are aligned to stimulus onset (red vertical line at time = 0). Bin size for peristimulus time histogram (bottom) is 200 ms. Red box highlights responses passing statistical criteria.

Modern research in neuroscience has furthered this representational stance, highlighting the social adaptability of these mirroring responses. Numerous fMRI studies have demonstrated that when we observe another individual’s goal-directed actions (versus other actions with no meaningful intent), traditional ROIs associated with the MNS are activated (e.g., dACC, inferior frontal gyrus (IFG), inferior parietal lobule (IPL), pre-supplementary motor area (preSMA); de Lange et al., 2008; Guionnet et al., 2012), which often co-occur with “mentalizing” ROIs that activate when relating to others (e.g., mPFC, posterior cingulate cortex (PCC), temporoparietal junction (TPJ), Van Overwalle and Baetens, 2009; Becchio et al., 2012; see Figures 1A,B). Similar results have also been observed in interactive dyad studies using EEG, where the social relation to the target modulates key action-related ERP components (e.g., contingent negative variation [CNV]; Kourtis et al., 2010) and μ-wave suppression (Hogeveen et al., 2014; but also see Braadbaart et al., 2013). While none of these studies prove the existence of a mediating role for higher-order representations, they do suggest that we have dedicated cognitive capacities that are tuned to the social relevance of others’ actions.

One interesting aspect of mirroring in the social environment is the possible role of the self (Mitchell, 2009). Specifically, psychological studies show that the self-concept is used as a starting point for attribution of mental states and attitudes to others, supporting the anchoring-and-adjustment view (Epley and Gilovich, 2001; Epley et al., 2004; Jenkins et al., 2008; Tamir and Mitchell, 2010). Neurally, mirroring often activates regions (like anterior intraparietal sulcus (aIPS), posterior superior temporal sulcus (pSTS), and PMC; see Figure 1A) that complement the “mentalizing” system (involving the TPJ and MPFC; see Figure 1B). Moreover, studies that use single-pulse TMS (which measure motor-evoked potentials [MEPs]) suggest that social perspective-taking and goal-directedness impacts motor preparation during very early processing stages (Obhi et al., 2011; Sartori et al., 2011; Hogeveen and Obhi, 2012; Cardellicchio et al., 2013; Senna et al., 2014). In sum, it appears that one way mirroring adapts to the social context is via mechanisms that involve the self and that progress in the debate about the representational nature of mirroring could be made by analyzing these mechanisms more in-depth.

Overall, while the above studies do not necessarily show that the mirroring mechanism is inherently representational, they do again suggest that the social nature of observed actions results in the dynamic adjustment of our own “smart” imitation. Partly as a result of such evidence, the non-representational mirroring theories have to be formulated (or reformulated) to explain how context-sensitivity could result less from higher-order representations, and more from simpler variables such as sensorimotor training, perception-action links, and developmental interactions with the social environment—which we move on to next.

Support for Non-Representational Frameworks

Recently, newer theories have been proposed for mirroring that reverse the logic underlying representational models. For example, one major non-representational framework proposes that “mirror neurons” are formed as a result of a domain-general learning mechanism that pairs contingent and contiguous perception and action (Heyes, 2011). According to this theory, spontaneous imitation can still adapt to context because different perception-action links can be selectively triggered in a particular setting (i.e., contextual modification). Critically however, the MNS does not code the goal-directed nature of observed actions, nor does it necessarily even strictly “mirror” those perceived behaviors (Cook and Bird, 2013; Cook et al., 2014). Other non-representational accounts for mirroring echo this same general sentiment, but instead argue that action-understanding is purely motoric in nature and based within the specific neural function of the MNS (Sinigaglia, 2009), which is then developed through supportive environmental interactions like narrative and social observation (Hutto, 2007). Generally though, non-representational frameworks question one of the fundamental aspects of representational models—the involvement of higher-order constructs that map another’s actions onto one’s own body, in order to solve this so-called “correspondence problem” (Iacoboni, 2009).

Much work in psychology and neuroscience on spontaneous imitation in humans appears to support this non-representational perspective. Overall, such studies have shown that mirroring can be quite automatic, yet is quickly reversible and contextually modifiable by low-level perceptual and motor factors. For example, normal patterns of automatic motor imitation can be reversed through brief periods of “counter-mirror training” (Catmur et al., 2007), and simple visual feedback improves facial imitative training (Cook et al., 2013). Furthermore, spontaneous imitation is influenced by low-level stimulus-related features, like visual context and stimulus velocity (Bisio et al., 2010), kinematic fidelity (Eaves et al., 2012), and testing environment (Cook et al., 2012b). Recall that under representational models, mirroring should be goal-directed; however, recent experiments have shown that this process does not always encode behavioral goals (Bird et al., 2007; Leighton et al., 2010a), persisting in social situations even against strong competitive incentives not to imitate (Belot et al., 2013) and even in settings when participants are clearly convinced that a model, such as an android, lacks any intentionality (Hofree et al., in press). While this is not necessarily direct evidence for non-representational accounts (since some representations might be unconscious), it definitely argues against the explicit representational notion of goals and intentions—especially given that these mirroring modifications often manifest quickly, unconsciously, and physiologically.

Further, research on spontaneous imitation in animals provides some of the most convincing evidence for non-representational frameworks, since higher-level representations should presumably be less relevant (or non-existent). In short, humans are not the only ones that can flexibly imitate (see Figure 2): past work has demonstrated spontaneous imitation in primates (Byrne and Tanner, 2006; Ferrari et al., 2006; Bard, 2007; Voelkl and Huber, 2007; Haun and Call, 2008; Dindo et al., 2010), birds (Fawcett et al., 2002; Zentall, 2004; Mui et al., 2008), rats (Heyes et al., 1994), and even dogs (Miller et al., 2009). In fact, even in animals, spontaneous imitation seems to be socially specific and selective. As examples, capuchin monkeys display greater affiliation towards humans who imitate them (Paukner et al., 2009) and dogs can selectively imitate a human behavior that is more preferential in nature (Range et al., 2007). In short, these studies showing contextual imitation in animals challenge the idea that higher-order, explicit representations drive the flexible and efficient social adjustment of imitative responses.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Demonstrations of spontaneous imitation in non-humans. Two examples of a neonatal macaque’s imitative response to (A) mouth opening and (B) tongue protrusion (reprinted from Ferrari et al., 2006). (C) Experimenter and female orangutan (Pongo pygmaeus) interacting in the contingent/matching condition showing an example of testing behavior (reprinted from Haun and Call (2008) with permission from Elsevier). (D) Apparatus with dog at the start of a test trial (top panel), and apparatus as dog is starting to make a screen-push response as test for imitation (bottom panel) (reprinted from Miller et al. (2009) with permission from Elsevier). (E) Starlings engaging in a two-action method task for imitative learning, with a push demonstrator (top panel) and a pull demonstrator (bottom panel) (reprinted from Fawcett et al. (2002) with permission from Elsevier).

Moreover, other non-human examples of imitation further highlight this possibility of a more “radical”, non-representational mirroring account. For instance, dolphins have been shown to have an advanced capacity for social spontaneous imitation, but this appears to be largely dependent on perception-action interactions with the environment. Specifically, when dolphins are blindfolded, they still copy target behaviors, but they change to a strategy that is more dependent on echolocation (i.e., detecting relevant behaviors through sound), rather than traditional visual routes of perception. Consequently, the authors posit that “such flexibility in changing perceptual routes demonstrates that the dolphin’s imitation was not automatically elicited, but rather results from an intentional, problem-solving approach to imitation [that utilizes the surrounding environment]” (Jaakkola et al., 2013). While numerous examples exist for this perception-action strategy in adjusting to the environment, not all based in the literature on spontaneous imitation (e.g., mate selection by crickets, pack hunting by wolves, etc.; Wilson and Golonka, 2013), the key point here is that social adaptation (including imitative behaviors) can be perceptually grounded without the need for representational mediation, at least in these non-human subjects.

Similarly, other work on “embodied” robots supports this non-representational notion that imitative behaviors can be entrained within the environment (e.g., via hierarchical optimization learning strategies; Billard et al., 2004; Argall et al., 2009). Interestingly, these methods can actually result in socially and emotionally responsive humanoids (Breazeal, 2003). Such spontaneous imitation in robots can even be “goal-directed”, where task behaviors are preferentially selected (Calinon et al., 2005), and these “representations” are developed purely through autonomous interactions with the physical environment (Ijspeert et al., 2002; Wischmann et al., 2006; Gigliotta and Nolfi, 2008). These findings are especially intriguing, given that non-human agents obviously cannot depend on internal cognitive resources, which would be necessary for imitation to occur according to representational models.

In sum, non-representational frameworks emphasize that mirroring responses usually seen in spontaneous imitation are perceptually and motorically grounded within the greater context of the social environment—and not solely through the manipulation of higher-order representations. This idea is supported by research demonstrating that spontaneous imitation can occur quickly and implicitly, responding to biologically implausible or impossible actions (Liepelt and Brass, 2010) or persisting in situations that make little sense from a social perspective (Cook et al., 2012a; Hofree et al., in press). Intriguingly, this non-representational mirroring account also follows across other areas of literature, given “smart” imitation findings in non-human agents, like robots and animals (see the following for a review: Huber et al., 2009; de Waal and Ferrari, 2010; Gawronski and Cesario, 2013).

Conclusion and Future Directions

In this mini-review, we have addressed a fundamental debate surrounding research and theory on mirroring—the role of mental representations. We argued that spontaneous imitation highlights the flexible, dynamic, yet still embodied aspects of mirroring—even in the absence of higher-order representations. Note that these frameworks do not have to be mutually exclusive on all fronts. For instance, both accounts posit that developmental experience and social context can modify mirroring responses (albeit, to different extents). Thus, while acknowledging that these models contain certain areas of overlap, the most valuable empirical advances will be made in investigating when and how these divergent imitative patterns manifest.

While this is indeed a difficult question to address, we believe that investigations of mirroring within the social context will be most informative: as examples, while non-representational studies have shown modulations of “automatic” imitation through the manipulation of low-level factors (e.g., stimulus-related perceptual cues), such paradigms often strip these stimuli of their real-world social relevance, where mirroring (and the use of representations) could be the most crucial. Also, higher-order representations may be especially useful with mirroring in novel social situations (where “mentalizing” is required), and the self is used to “bootstrap” mental states onto the other person (e.g., Mitchell, 2009; Tamir and Mitchell, 2010). On the other hand, more straightforward social scenarios may not require the instantiation of the self-concept as a reference in mirroring (or its related mental representations). Such an interpretation might suggest that the existence of representations in mirroring responses should not be the primary question, compared to examining how mirroring transitions between simple and “smart” states, especially within varying social situations.

Explorations into such questions will prove especially beneficial with newer advances in both technology (e.g., single-unit recordings in humans during action-observation and performance; Mukamel et al., 2010; see Figures 1C,D) and methodology (e.g., using “counter-mirror training” to study imitation in social situations; Catmur et al., 2007). Additionally, non-representational frameworks do not have to be “all-or-nothing”, since there are multiple levels of interpretation that can be employed. For instance, while some non-representational mirroring accounts would posit a more “radical” mindset (whereby these responses are purely driven by perception-action interactions with the environment, thus replacing complex internal representations; Wilson and Golonka, 2013), others may argue that higher-order representations are just another moderator of an otherwise non-representational mirroring process. In turn, evaluating the functional role of representations in mirroring would be especially informative, where future studies not only explore the co-occurrence of goal-directed “mentalizing” ROIs (e.g., via fMRI), but also what happens to mirroring when these ROIs are impeded (e.g., via TMS)?

Going forward, we argue for a flexible embodiment framework that is both simple and “smart”—a view that offers a reconciliation among “traditional” symbolic perspectives in cognitive neuroscience and more “radical”, non-representational theories of embodied processing. Critically, such a mindset will encourage new insights into the interpretation of modern (and seemingly divergent) findings from numerous fields across psychology and neuroscience—particularly on when and how these embodied imitative responses are engaged.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

Evan W. Carr conducted this work with government support under and awarded by the United States Department of Defense (DoD), National Defense Science and Engineering Graduate (NDSEG) Fellowship, 32 CFR 168a.

References

Argall, B. D., Chernova, S., Veloso, M., and Browning, B. (2009). A survey of robot learning from demonstration. Rob. Auton. Syst. 57, 469–483. doi: 10.1016/j.robot.2008.10.024

CrossRef Full Text

Bard, K. A. (2007). Neonatal imitation in chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) tested with two paradigms. Anim. Cogn. 10, 233–242. doi: 10.1007/s10071-006-0062-3

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Barrett, L. (2011). Beyond the Brain: How the Body and the Environment Shape Cognition. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

Becchio, C., Cavallo, A., Begliomini, C., Sartori, L., Feltrin, G., and Castiello, U. (2012). Social grasping: from mirroring to mentalizing. Neuroimage 61, 240–248. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.03.013

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Belot, M., Crawford, V. P., and Heyes, C. (2013). Players of matching pennies automatically imitate opponents’ gestures against strong incentives. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A 110, 2763–2768. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1209981110

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Billard, A., Epars, Y., Calinon, S., Schaal, S., and Cheng, G. (2004). Discovering optimal imitation strategies. Rob. Auton. Syst. 47, 69–77. doi: 10.1016/s0921-8890(04)00038-7

CrossRef Full Text

Bird, G., Brindley, R., Leighton, J., and Heyes, C. (2007). General processes, rather than “goals,” explain imitation errors. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 33, 1158–1169. doi: 10.1037/0096-1523.33.5.1158

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Bisio, A., Stucchi, N., Jacono, M., Fadiga, L., and Pozzo, T. (2010). Automatic versus voluntary motor imitation: effect of visual context and stimulus velocity. PLoS One 5:e13506. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0013506

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Blakemore, S. J., and Decety, J. (2001). From the perception of action to the understanding of intention. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2, 561–567. doi: 10.1038/35086023

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Bourgeois, P., and Hess, U. (2008). The impact of social context on mimicry. Biol. Psychol. 77, 343–352. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2007

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Braadbaart, L., Williams, J. H., and Waiter, G. D. (2013). Do mirror neuron areas mediate mu rhythm suppression during imitation and action observation? Int. J. Psychophysiol. 89, 99–105. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2013.05.019

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Wohlschläger, A., and Prinz, W. (2000). Compatibility between observed and executed finger movements: comparing symbolic, spatial and imitative cues. Brain Cogn. 44, 124–143. doi: 10.1006/brcg.2000.1225

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Breazeal, C. (2003). Emotion and sociable humanoid robots. Int. J. Hum. Comput. Stud. 59, 119–155. doi: 10.1016/s1071-5819(03)00018-1

CrossRef Full Text

Byrne, R. W., and Tanner, J. E. (2006). Gestural imitation by a gorilla: evidence and nature of the capacity. Int. J. Psychol. Ther. 6, 215–231.

Calinon, S., Guenter, F., and Billard, A. (2005). “Goal-directed imitation in a humanoid Robot,” in Proceedings of the International Conference on Robotics and Automation (ICRA 2005) (Barcelona: IEEE), 299–304.

Cardellicchio, P., Sinigaglia, C., and Costantini, M. (2013). Grasping affordances with the other’s hand: a TMS study. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 8, 455–459. doi: 10.1093/scan/nss017

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Carr, E. W., Winkielman, P., and Oveis, C. (2014). Transforming the mirror: power fundamentally changes facial responding to emotional expressions. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 143, 997–1003. doi: 10.1037/a0034972

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Catmur, C., Walsh, V., and Heyes, C. (2007). Sensorimotor learning configures the human mirror system. Curr. Biol. 17, 1527–1531. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2007.08.006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Catmur, C., Walsh, V., and Heyes, C. (2009). Associative sequence learning: the role of experience in the development of imitation and the mirror system. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 364, 2369–2380. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2009.0048

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Chartrand, T. L., and van Baaren, R. (2009). Human mimicry. Adv. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 41, 219–274. doi: 10.1016/S0065-2601(08)00405-X

CrossRef Full Text

Chemero, A. (2009). Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Cook, R., and Bird, G. (2013). Do mirror neurons really mirror and do they really code for action goals? Cortex 49, 2944–2945. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2013.05.006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Cook, R., Bird, G., Catmur, C., Press, C., and Heyes, C. (2014). Mirror neurons: from origin to function. Behav. Brain Sci. 37, 177–192. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X13000903

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Cook, R., Bird, G., Lünser, G., Huck, S., and Heyes, C. (2012a). Automatic imitation in a strategic context: players of rock–paper–scissors imitate opponents’ gestures. Proc. Biol. Sci. 279, 780–786. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2011.1024

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Cook, R., Dickinson, A., and Heyes, C. (2012b). Contextual modulation of mirror and countermirror sensorimotor associations. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 141, 774–787. doi: 10.1037/a0027561

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Cook, R., Johnston, A., and Heyes, C. (2013). Facial self-imitation: objective measurement reveals no improvement without visual feedback. Psychol. Sci. 24, 93–98. doi: 10.1177/0956797612452568

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

de Lange, F. P., Spronk, M., Willems, R. M., Toni, I., and Bekkering, H. (2008). Complementary systems for understanding action intentions. Curr. Biol. 18, 454–457. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2008.02.057

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

de Waal, F., and Ferrari, P. F. (2010). Towards a bottom-up perspective on animal and human cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 14, 201–207. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2010.03.003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Dindo, M., Thierry, B., de Waal, F., and Whiten, A. (2010). Conditional copying fidelity in capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella). J. Comp. Psychol. 124, 29–37. doi: 10.1037/a0018005

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Eaves, D. L., Turgeon, M., and Vogt, S. (2012). Automatic imitation in rhythmical actions: kinematic fidelity and the effects of compatibility, delay and visual monitoring. PLoS One 7:e46728. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0046728

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Epley, N., and Gilovich, T. (2001). Putting adjustment back in the anchoring and adjustment heuristic: differential processing of self-generated and experimenter-provided anchors. Psychol. Sci. 12, 391–396. doi: 10.1111/1467-9280.00372

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Epley, N., Keysar, B., Van Boven, L., and Gilovich, T. (2004). Perspective taking as egocentric anchoring and adjustment. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 87, 327–339. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.87.3.327

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Fawcett, T. W., Skinner, A. M., and Goldsmith, A. R. (2002). A test of imitative learning in starlings using a two-action method with an enhanced ghost control. Anim. Behav. 64, 547–556. doi: 10.1006/anbe.2002.3092

CrossRef Full Text

Ferrari, P. F., Visalberghi, E., Paukner, A., Fogassi, L., Ruggiero, A., and Suomi, S. J. (2006). Neonatal imitation in rhesus macaques. PLoS Biol. 4:e302. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.0040302

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gallagher, S. (2007). Simulation trouble. Soc. Neurosci. 2, 353–365. doi: 10.1080/17470910601183549

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gallese, V. (2003a). The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: the quest for a common mechanism. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 358, 517–528. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2002.1234

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gallese, V. (2003b). A neuroscientific grasp of concepts: from control to representation. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 358, 1231–1240. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2003.1315

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gawronski, B., and Cesario, J. (2013). Of mice and men: what animal research can tell us about context effects on automatic responses in humans. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 17, 187–215. doi: 10.1177/1088868313480096

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gigliotta, O., and Nolfi, S. (2008). On the coupling between agent internal and agent/environmental dynamics: development of spatial representations in evolving autonomous robots. Adapt. Behav. 16, 148–165. doi: 10.1177/1059712308089184

CrossRef Full Text

Goldman, A. I., and Sripada, C. S. (2005). Simulationist models of face-based emotion recognition. Cognition 94, 193–213. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2004.01.005

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Guéguen, N., and Martin, A. (2009). Incidental similarity facilitates behavioral mimicry. Soc. Psychol. 40, 88–92. doi: 10.1027/1864-9335.40.2.88

CrossRef Full Text

Guionnet, S., Nadel, J., Bertasi, E., Sperduti, M., Delaveau, P., and Fossati, P. (2012). Reciprocal imitation: toward a neural basis of social interaction. Cereb. Cortex 22, 971–978. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhr177

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hamilton, A. F. (2013). The mirror neuron system contributes to social responding. Cortex 49, 2957–2959. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2013.08.012

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Haun, D., and Call, J. (2008). Imitation recognition in great apes. Curr. Biol. 18, 288–290. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2008.02.031

CrossRef Full Text

Hess, U., and Fischer, A. (2013). Emotional mimicry as social regulation. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 17, 142–157. doi: 10.1177/1088868312472607

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Heyes, C. (2011). Automatic imitation. Psychol. Bull. 137, 463–483. doi: 10.1037/a0022288

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Heyes, C. M., Jaldow, E., Nokes, T., and Dawson, G. R. (1994). Imitation in rats (Rattus norvegicus): the role of demonstrator action. Behav. Processes 32, 173–182. doi: 10.1016/0376-6357(94)90074-4

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hofree, G., Ruvolo, P., Stewart-Bartlett, M., and Winkielman, P. (in press). Bridging the mechanical and human mind: spontaneous facial mimicry of a humanoid robot. PLoS One.

Hogeveen, J., and Obhi, S. S. (2012). Social interaction enhances motor resonance for observed human actions. J. Neurosci. 32, 5984–5989. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5938-11.2012

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hogeveen, J., Chartrand, T. L., and Obhi, S. S. (2014). Social mimicry enhances mu-suppression during action observation. Cereb. Cortex doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhu016. [Epub ahead of print].

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Huber, L., Range, F., Voelkl, B., Szucsich, A., Virányi, Z., and Miklosi, A. (2009). The evolution of imitation: what do the capacities of non-human animals tell us about the mechanisms of imitation? Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 364, 2299–2309. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2009.0060

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hutto, D. D. (2007). The narrative practice hypothesis: origins and applications to folk psychology. Royal Inst. Philos. Suppl. 60, 43–68. doi: 10.1017/s1358246107000033

CrossRef Full Text

Iacoboni, M. (2009). Imitation, empathy, and mirror neurons. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 60, 653–670. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163604

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Ijspeert, A. J., Nakanishi, J., and Schaal, S. (2002). “Movement imitation with nonlinear dynamical systems in humanoid robots,” in Proceedings of the International Conference on Robotics and Automation (ICRA 2002) Vol. 2 (Washington, DC: IEEE), 1398–1403.

Jaakkola, K., Guarino, E., Rodriguez, M., and Hecksher, J. (2013). Switching strategies: a dolphin’s use of passive and active acoustics to imitate motor actions. Anim. Cogn. 16, 701–709. doi: 10.1007/s10071-013-0605-3

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Jenkins, A. C., Macrae, C. N., and Mitchell, J. P. (2008). Repetition suppression of ventromedial prefrontal activity during judgments of self and others. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A 105, 4507–4512. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0708785105

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keysers, C., and Gazzola, V. (2006). Towards a unifying neural theory of social cognition. Prog. Brain Res. 156, 379–401. doi: 10.1016/s0079-6123(06)56021-2

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Kourtis, D., Sebanz, N., and Knoblich, G. (2010). Favouritism in the motor system: social interaction modulates action simulation. Biol. Lett. 6, 758–761. doi: 10.1098/rsbl.2010.0478

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Lakin, J. L., and Chartrand, T. L. (2003). Using nonconscious behavioral mimicry to create affiliation and rapport. Psychol. Sci. 14, 334–339. doi: 10.1111/1467-9280.14481

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Leighton, J., Bird, G., and Heyes, C. (2010a). “Goals” are not an integral component of imitation. Cognition 114, 423–435. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2009.11.001

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Leighton, J., Bird, G., Orsini, C., and Heyes, C. (2010b). Social attitudes modulate automatic imitation. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 46, 905–910. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2010.07.001

CrossRef Full Text

Liepelt, R., and Brass, M. (2010). Top-down modulation of motor priming by belief about animacy. Exp. Psychol. 57, 221–227. doi: 10.1027/1618-3169/a000028

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Likowski, K. U., Mühlberger, A., Seibt, B., Pauli, P., and Weyers, P. (2008). Modulation of facial mimicry by attitudes. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 44, 1065–1072. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2007.10.007

CrossRef Full Text

Meltzoff, A. N., and Decety, J. (2003). What imitation tells us about social cognition: a rapprochement between developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 358, 491–500. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2002.1261

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Miller, H. C., Rayburn-Reeves, R., and Zentall, T. R. (2009). Imitation and emulation by dogs using a bidirectional control procedure. Behav. Processes 80, 109–114. doi: 10.1016/j.beproc.2008.09.011

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mitchell, J. P. (2009). Social psychology as a natural kind. Trends Cogn. Sci. 13, 246–251. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.03.008

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mui, R., Haselgrove, M., Pearce, J., and Heyes, C. (2008). Automatic imitation in budgerigars. Proc. Biol. Sci. 275, 2547–2553. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2008.0566

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mukamel, R., Ekstrom, A. D., Kaplan, J., Iacoboni, M., and Fried, I. (2010). Single-neuron responses in humans during execution and observation of actions. Curr. Biol. 20, 750–756. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2010.02.045

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L., Winkielman, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., and Ric, F. (2005). Embodiment in attitudes, social perception and emotion. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 9, 184–211. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr0903_1

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Obhi, S. S., Hogeveen, J., and Pascual-Leone, A. (2011). Resonating with others: the effects of self-construal type on motor cortical output. J. Neurosci. 31, 14531–14535. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3186-11.2011

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Paukner, A., Suomi, S. J., Visalberghi, E., and Ferrari, P. F. (2009). Capuchin monkeys display affiliation toward humans who imitate them. Science 325, 880–883. doi: 10.1126/science.1176269

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Preston, S. D., and De Waal, F. (2002). Empathy: its ultimate and proximate bases. Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 1–20. doi: 10.1017/s0140525x02000018

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Range, F., Viranyi, Z., and Huber, L. (2007). Selective imitation in domestic dogs. Curr. Biol. 17, 868–872. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2007.04.026

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Reed, C. L., and McIntosh, D. N. (2013). The response is more than reflection: mirror neurons function within social contexts. Cortex 49, 2960–2961. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2013.04.004

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Rizzolatti, G., and Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror-neuron system. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 169–192. doi: 10.1146/annurev.neuro.27.070203.144230

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Sartori, L., Cavallo, A., Bucchioni, G., and Castiello, U. (2011). Corticospinal excitability is specifically modulated by the social dimension of observed actions. Exp. Brain Res. 211, 557–568. doi: 10.1007/s00221-011-2650-y

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Semin, G. R., and Cacioppo, J. T. (2009). “From embodied representation to co-regulation,” in Mirror Neuron Systems, ed Jaime A. Pineda (New York, NY: Humana Press), 107–120. doi: 10.1007/978-1-59745-479-7_5

CrossRef Full Text

Senna, I., Bolognini, N., and Maravita, A. (2014). Grasping with the foot: goal and motor expertise in action observation. Hum. Brain Mapp. 35, 1750–1760. doi: 10.1002/hbm.22289

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Sinigaglia, C. (2009). Mirror in action. J. Conscious. Stud. 16, 309–334.

Tamir, D. I., and Mitchell, J. P. (2010). Neural correlates of anchoring-and-adjustment during mentalizing. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A 107, 10827–10832. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1003242107

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Van Overwalle, F. (2009). Social cognition and the brain: a meta-analysis. Hum. Brain Mapp. 30, 829–858. doi: 10.1002/hbm.20547

CrossRef Full Text

Van Overwalle, F., and Baetens, K. (2009). Understanding others’ actions and goals by mirror and mentalizing systems: a meta-analysis. Neuroimage 48, 564–584. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.06.009

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Voelkl, B., and Huber, L. (2007). Imitation as faithful copying of a novel technique in marmoset monkeys. PLoS One 2:e611. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0000611

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wang, Y., and Hamilton, A. F. de C. (2012). Social top-down response modulation (STORM): a model of the control of mimicry in social interaction. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6:153. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2012.00153

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wang, Y., Newport, R., and Hamilton, A. F. de C. (2011). Eye contact enhances mimicry of intransitive hand movements. Biol. Lett. 7, 7–10. doi: 10.1098/rsbl.2010.0279

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Weyers, P., Mühlberger, A., Kund, A., Hess, U., and Pauli, P. (2009). Modulation of facial reactions to avatar emotional faces by nonconscious competition priming. Psychophysiology 46, 328–335. doi: 10.1111/j.1469-8986.2008.00771.x

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wilson, A. D., and Golonka, S. (2013). Embodied cognition is not what you think it is. Front. Psychol. 4:58. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wischmann, S., Hülse, M., Knabe, J. F., and Pasemann, F. (2006). Synchronization of internal neural rhythms in multi-robotic systems. Adapt. Behav. 14, 117–127. doi: 10.1177/105971230601400203

CrossRef Full Text

Zentall, T. R. (2004). Action imitation in birds. Learn. Behav. 32, 15–23. doi: 10.3758/bf03196003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: embodiment, imitation, social learning, mimicry, mirror neurons

Citation: Carr EW and Winkielman P (2014) When mirroring is both simple and “smart”: how mimicry can be embodied, adaptive, and non-representational. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:505. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00505

Received: 27 March 2014; Accepted: 23 June 2014;
Published online: 14 July 2014.

Edited by:

Andrew D. Wilson, Leeds Metropolitan University, UK

Reviewed by:

Sören Krach, Philipps-University Marburg, Germany
Mariella Pazzaglia, University of Rome La Sapienza, Italy

Copyright © 2014 Carr and Winkielman. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Evan W. Carr, Department of Psychology, University of California - San Diego, 9500 Gilman Drive, La Jolla, CA 92093-0109, USA e-mail: Ewcarr@ucsd.edu

Download