Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 27 March 2013
Sec. Social and Evolutionary Neuroscience

Psychopathy, adaptation, and disorder

  • 1Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Queen's University, Kingston, ON, Canada
  • 2Department of Psychology, Queen's University, Kingston, ON, Canada
  • 3Department of Psychology, University of Saskatchewan, Saskatoon, SK, Canada
  • 4School of Psychology, University of Ottawa, Ottawa, ON, Canada
  • 5Tulloch Mapping Solutions, Ottawa, ON, Canada
  • 6Waypoint Centre for Mental Health, Penetanguishene, ON, Canada

In a recent study, we found a negative association between psychopathy and violence against genetic relatives. We interpreted this result as a form of nepotism and argued that it failed to support the hypothesis that psychopathy is a mental disorder, suggesting instead that it supports the hypothesis that psychopathy is an evolved life history strategy. This interpretation and subsequent arguments have been challenged in a number of ways. Here, we identify several misunderstandings regarding the harmful dysfunction definition of mental disorder as it applies to psychopathy and regarding the meaning of nepotism. Furthermore, we examine the evidence provided by our critics that psychopathy is associated with other disorders, and we offer a comment on their alternative model of psychopathy. We conclude that there remains little evidence that psychopathy is the product of dysfunctional mechanisms.

Psychopathy poses a significant problem to communal living: psychopaths are far more likely than others to engage in harmful behaviors ranging from the parasitic to the homicidal. In this light, we thank Leedom and Hartoonian Almas (2012) for their comments on Krupp et al. (2012), as they provide us with an opportunity to clarify the arguments we made and to continue working toward a sophisticated and testable evolution-minded model of psychopathy that may help to address this problem.

Following Wakefield's (1992) influential concept of harmful dysfunction, Krupp et al. (2012; see also Harris et al., 2001a,b) argued that psychopathy may be considered a mental disorder only if there is compelling evidence that it (1) leads to harm to self or others and (2) is caused by a failure of psychological mechanisms to serve the functions for which they were designed by natural selection. In keeping with the first criterion, we accept without qualification that psychopathy causes disproportionate harm to others. What we challenge is the claim that there is evidence, compelling or otherwise, of the second criterion—that psychopathy is the result of dysfunctional psychological mechanisms in the sense implied above.

We take it as given that the brains of psychopaths differ from those of nonpsychopaths in systematic ways. Without such differences, psychopaths could not be reliably set apart in their cognition and behavior from nonpsychopaths. But difference is not isomorphic with dysfunction. For instance, although the brains of men and women have much in common, they must also be different on average, as must the brains of young and old, married and single, androphile and gynephile, Anglophone and Francophone, and so on, even if these brain differences are solely the result of differences of experience. While the life sciences have begun to recognize that such differences do not inherently reflect disorder, the relationship between difference and disorder nevertheless continues to bedevil the study of mental health.

An argument for dysfunction must marshal supporting evidence, and this must be distinguishable from evidence of difference. For example, researchers should not assume without corroboration that a burglar was mentally disordered simply because he committed theft, any more than they should assume that a child was mentally disordered for failing to share her toys with her siblings. Chronic malefaction, however, is often construed—groundlessly, we hasten to add—as proof of disorder. And so, while researchers enthusiastically catalogue the neural and cognitive particulars of inveterate misbehavior, their efforts do not necessarily provide evidence of the failure of mechanisms to perform their selected functions.

There are many signs that mental mechanisms are not performing in accordance with their adaptive design, including injuries to the brain, obstetrical complications, excessive levels of fluctuating asymmetry, and other indications of neurodevelopmental perturbation. As discussed in our article and the references cited therein, there is no evidence that any of these indicators covary positively with psychopathy. Other signs of mental dysfunction might include behaviors that would have led to ineluctable inclusive fitness costs in ancestral environments. An individual's inclusive fitness is the net effect of its genotype on its own fitness (d, for direct fitness), including effects on lineal descendants, and on the fitness of others bearing nonrandom genotypes (i, for indirect fitness), including effects on collateral kin (Hamilton, 1964, 1970). Upregulating, downregulating, or taking adaptations entirely “offline” may have led to inclusive fitness decrements or increments, depending upon the conditions under which these adaptations would have been expected to operate. For instance, worker sterility has independently evolved numerous times among the eusocial Hymenoptera and other eusocial taxa (e.g., aphids, termites, and thrips). What might appear at first blush to be an unmitigated failure of design—the reproductive function of scores of individuals has been downregulated or taken offline, in many cases permanently—is anything but: eusociality has evolved only under conditions of high genetic relatedness between reproductives and workers, in keeping with the hypothesis that workers benefit their inclusive fitness more from rearing their full siblings together than from rearing their own offspring alone (Hughes et al., 2008). Hence, even gross variation in behavioral or physical phenotype may be due either to developmental error and injury or to adaptive design, in much the same way that the polymorphisms of the army ant Eciton burchellii (Franks, 1985, 1986) or male bluegill sunfish (Lepomis macrocheris; Gross and Charnov, 1980; Gross, 1991) reflect adaptive specialization to different strategic interests.

The task at hand, then, is to discover whether differences in mental functioning historically entailed inclusive fitness costs and to furthermore identify their sources. For example, failing memory systems cause profound deficits in the ability to navigate one's physical and social universe, as evidenced by individuals with anterograde amnesia (Scoville and Milner, 1957), dementia (Bowen et al., 1997), and schizophrenia (Frith and Done, 1989; Nathaniel-James and Frith, 1996; Corcoran and Frith, 2003). These memory failures seem neither to provide any fitness advantage nor to be compensated for by modified or alternative mechanisms, and so would have caused a decrease in the inclusive fitness of those afflicted with them. Concomitant with these failures are indicators of pathology and disturbance, including brain damage (Scoville and Milner, 1957), minor physical anomalies (Weinberg et al., 2007), pre- and perinatal complications (Cannon et al., 2002), excess fluctuating asymmetry (Markow, 1992), and oxidative stress (Bennett et al., 2009; Bitanihirwe and Woo, 2011), as would be expected were they symptomatic of a mental disorder.

The inclusive fitness effect is the maximand of selection (Grafen, 2006), and the corresponding condition for which an action is favored by selection is given by d + i > 0. Using this formulation, it becomes plain that individuals pursuing a psychopathic “strategy” as we and others have envisioned it—one of persistent social exploitation—must, on balance, behave in ways that historically maximized benefits and minimized costs to d, i, or both. Thus, for a start, they cannot impose costs on their lineal descendants and on collateral kin that, after weighting by relatedness, are disproportionate to the benefits of their actions. Psychopathy seems to be associated with an upregulation of sexual psychology and associated behaviors (Quinsey et al., 1995; Lalumière and Quinsey, 1996; Harris et al., 2007b), and this is mirrored by evidence that psychopathic offenders have at least as many offspring as nonpsychopathic controls and may even have slightly more (Harris et al., 2007b; Pulkkinen et al., 2009; Vachon et al., 2012; cf. Power et al., 2013). We do not know with any certainty what fecundity advantage psychopaths would have enjoyed in ancestral environments, but its effects on inclusive fitness would have been undercut by any imposition of significant costs to offspring and other genealogical kin.

Following the logic outlined above, the arguments for dysfunction and for adaptation generate rival hypotheses. If, on the one hand, psychopathy is a mental disorder sensu Wakefield (1992), then we would hypothesize that psychopathic offenders, relative to their nonpsychopathic counterparts, ought not to behave nepotistically, because their psychology has been profoundly affected by a maladaptive course of development. After all, it would be peculiar for misdirected ontogenetic processes to leave nepotistic devices alone when they have had such sweeping, downregulatory effects on related systems, such as empathy, remorse, and guilt (Hare, 1993). Indeed, as discussed in Krupp et al. (2012), perpetrators who behave violently toward kin carry an elevated risk of mental disorder diagnosis (Daly and Wilson, 1988a; Harris et al., 2007a). If, on the other hand, psychopathy represents an alternative life strategy of persistent social exploitation, then we would hypothesize that psychopaths ought to behave nepotistically in that they limit the costs they impose on genetic relatives. Thus, nepotistic discrimination can be used as an indicator of mental disorder.

In our study, we failed to support the former hypothesis and, consequently, supported the latter: scores on the Psychopathy Checklist-Revised (PCL-R; Hare, 1991), an archetypal measure of psychopathy, were significantly negatively associated with victim-offender relatedness in the index offenses of violent offenders. This finding, which implies that psychopathy is associated with benefits rather than costs to inclusive fitness (because harm was likely allocated to negative relatives), was not explained by measures of distance or frequency of dispersal, and it was not explained by a measure of inbreeding avoidance, though it must of course be explained by something. When the sample was restricted to offenders who did not coreside with kin, the direction of the association remained unchanged, though it was no longer statistically significant, continuing to imply that psychopathy was not associated with any cost to an individual's inclusive fitness. All of this suggests that, in the context of violence, psychopathic offenders behaved at least as nepotistically, and possibly more so, than did their nonpsychopathic counterparts.

Broadly, Leedom and Hartoonian Almas (2012) criticize Krupp et al. (2012) from two positions. Their first point of disagreement regards evidence of nepotism among psychopathic individuals. While they do not dispute our findings, they argue that these findings do not constitute evidence of nepotism for three reasons: (1) psychopaths may nevertheless harm genealogical relatives in ways not measured by our study; (2) a majority of psychopathic offenders are nonviolent, and so our use of violence as a measure of harm is inappropriate; and (3) a reduction in harm to relatives is not the same as nepotistic help.

We acknowledged (1) when we wrote: “[i]t is possible, for instance, that the cumulative effects of psychopathy on an offender's kin, including negative reputational effects, are substantial, even though the costs of individual actions may be small” (Krupp et al., 2012, p. 5). Researchers are limited to the data they have in hand, however, and (as discussed by Leedom and Hartoonian Almas, 2012) no other study of sufficient quality exists that speaks to this problem. Regarding (2), violence would undoubtedly have had large effects on fitness relative to most other forms of social interaction, and so is relevant even when rare. Moreover, Leedom and Hartoonian Almas provide no evidence that “most psychopathic individuals are not violent” (p. 1). The PCL-R is a formidable individual-level predictor of violence in many forms (reviewed in Harris et al., 2001b); if we cannot apply to psychopathic individuals data measuring violent behavior, to whom can such data be applied? Finally, and furthermore with respect to (1), studies of violence may provide unique psychological insights, because violence is rarely caused by anything short of powerful concerns and because reports of violence are bound to be considerably less biased than reports of other sorts of behavior (Daly and Wilson, 1988a,b). To deny the importance of violence because it is rare is to deny all that studies of violence have contributed to our understanding of parental and familial love (e.g., Wilson et al., 1980; Daly and Wilson, 1982, 1988a,b; Harris et al., 2007a), sexual proprietariness (e.g., Daly et al., 1982; Daly and Wilson, 1988a,b; Wilson and Daly, 1992, 1993), and intrasexual competition (e.g., Wilson and Daly, 1985, 1997; Daly and Wilson, 1988a,b, 2010).

We are puzzled by (3), given that Leedom and Hartoonian Almas (2012) quote fully the following statement from Krupp et al. (2012, p. 2, emphasis added): “individuals executing well-designed strategies, a necessary feature of psychological adaptations, should tend to be nepotistic—providing aid to close genealogical kin and/or sparing them from harm.” As discussed here and in the original article, nepotistic systems are not required to help genealogical relatives; rather, they are required to discriminate between positive and negative relatives in such a way as to maximize the actor's inclusive fitness, which may entail helping kin when cooperation is favored or minimizing the costs to kin and instead imposing them on others when it is not. Simply put, a lack of violent harm need not be synonymous with help for it to qualify as an adaptive form of nepotism. Psychopathic individuals may not make for nice genetic relations, but they appear to make for worse nongenetic relations still.

Leedom and Hartoonian Almas's (2012) second point of disagreement concerns the way in which our study speaks to Wakefield's (1992) concept of mental disorder which, if the reader will recall, is defined as a psychological phenomenon that (1) causes harm to self or others and (2) is the result of a failure of one or more psychological mechanisms to perform the tasks for which they were designed. Curiously, Leedom and Hartoonian Almas focus only on the first criterion, stating that “Any ‘benefit’ of psychopathy according to Krupp et al. (2012) is in perpetuation of genes only. However, that psychopathic individuals might contribute to the gene pool, has no bearing on the definition of harm as conceptualized by Wakefield” (p. 1, emphasis added). This is true insofar as criterion (1) is concerned, but our analysis was concerned with criterion (2)—that the design of nepotistic psychology remains intact among psychopaths, providing further evidence in support of extant adaptation hypotheses and against mental disorder hypotheses. Leedom and Hartoonian Almas appear to have understood that all parties are in agreement on criterion (1), as they state “That psychopathy is associated with disastrous consequences for individuals and society was not disputed by the authors” (p. 1). Yet, they seem to have entirely overlooked the relevance of our study to criterion (2): the only measure of cost and benefit that matters with respect to Wakefield's (1992) dysfunction criterion is that which concerns the effect of an action on inclusive fitness.

Relatedly, Leedom and Hartoonian Almas (2012) disagree with our statement that “psychopathy is neither comorbid nor associated with the neurodevelopmental perturbations characteristic of other serious mental illnesses, such as psychosis and mental retardation” (Krupp et al., 2012, p. 1), arguing that psychopathy is associated with paranoid personality disorder (citing Blackburn and Maybury, 1985; Blackburn, 1998; Fullam and Dolan, 2006; McGregor et al., 2012) and Eysenck's concept of psychoticism (citing Eysenck and Eysenck, 1977; Corr, 2010); they further point to a study by Suchankova et al. (2012) showing that psychoticism is associated with schizophrenia. While we covered the issue of neurodevelopmental perturbations in Krupp et al. (2012) and elsewhere (Harris et al., 2001a; Lalumière et al., 2001), we must further examine the evidence that Leedom and Hartoonian Almas provide suggesting that psychopathy is comorbid with true mental illness. Unfortunately, we find this evidence wanting.

First, while psychopathy is comorbid with some personality disorders (e.g., antisocial personality disorder), none of them—paranoid personality disorder included—reflect psychosis. Moreover, it remains to be established whether any personality disorder may be characterized as a disorder in the sense meant by Wakefield (1992). Second, it is clear that Eysenck's concept of psychoticism is unusual, as it reflects tough-minded, antisocial, unempathic, egocentric, impulsive, and aggressive traits (Eysenck, 1992). These characteristics resemble psychopathy far more than they do psychosis. Third, neither Blackburn and Maybury (1985) nor Corr (2010) presented any data demonstrating that psychopathy and psychosis (as it is commonly understood) are comorbid; rather, they relied on associations between measures of psychopathy and Eysenck's psychoticism. All of this is tantamount to idiosyncratically defining psychosis as manifesting manipulation, callousness, lying, remorselessness, glibness, shallow affect, proneness to boredom, irresponsibility, impulsivity, poor behavior controls, criminal versatility (and so on), and then “discovering” that it is comorbid with psychopathy as assessed by the PCL-R. Fourth, Fullam and Dolan (2006) and McGregor et al. (2012) only studied patients with schizophrenia or schizophrenia spectrum conditions, reporting that PCL-R scores predicted violence in such samples; the title of Fullam and Dolan's article notwithstanding, this sort of work does not—indeed, cannot—bear on the question of whether psychopathy and schizophrenia are comorbid (i.e., associated with each other in the population). Finally, Suchankova et al. (2012) provided evidence of a link between schizophrenia and an amalgam of scores on the detachment and suspicion subscales of the Karolinska Scales of Personality, but it is not remotely clear how such a relationship speaks to the question of whether psychopathy and psychosis (as conventionally understood) are related.

Leedom and Hartoonian Almas (2012) argue that, “[r]ather than being ‘an adaptation’ psychopathy may represent a spandrel—a syndrome that arises as a consequence of other features” (p. 2). They then go on to sketch their own evolution-minded model of psychopathy as, if we understand it correctly, the upshot of selection on dominance systems. We cannot adequately address here whether this model better accounts for the unique features of psychopathy than do others. We can, however, point out that identifying psychopathy as a “spandrel” (Gould and Lewontin, 1979; see also Buss et al., 1998; Andrews et al., 2002) does not speak to the argument for dysfunction. A spandrel has no evolved function, and so cannot itself be dysfunctional. Hence, the mechanisms from which a spandrel manifests would themselves have to be dysfunctional to support an argument for dysfunction. In turn, the evidence for this would have to resemble that which has been outlined above: indications of neurodevelopmental perturbation and dysregulation of systems resulting in historical inclusive fitness costs. We arrive, then, back where we began: there is no evidence that psychopathy is the result of dysfunctional rather than merely different psychological mechanisms.

The disagreement between adaptation and disorder models of psychopathy does not rest solely on semantics. To the degree that one class of model better accounts for the psychology of psychopathy, it will also better help us to understand and, hopefully, to cope with psychopathy. If psychopathy is a mental disorder, the absence of indicators of developmental instability or intellectual, operational, or reproductive disadvantage strikes us as odd. Equally surprising, important aspects of nepotistic design appear to remain intact even when related emotional circuitry has been profoundly revised. Until such time as compelling evidence of dysfunction (rather than difference) is presented, it is imperative that we continue to develop and test alternative, functional hypotheses of psychopathy such as the frequency-dependent model posited by Harpending and Sobus (1987), Mealey (1995), Harris et al. (2001b), Lalumière et al. (2001), and others.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Paul Andrews and Paul Watson for comments and discussion.

References

Andrews, P. W., Gangestad, S. W., and Matthews, D. (2002). Adaptationism: how to carry out an exaptationist program. Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 489–553.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Bennett, S., Grant, M. M., and Aldred, S. (2009). Oxidative stress in vascular dementia and Alzheimer's disease: a common pathology. J. Alzheimers Dis. 17, 245–257.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Bitanihirwe, B. K. Y., and Woo, T. U. W. (2011). Oxidative stress in schizophrenia: an integrated approach. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 35, 878–893.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Blackburn, R. (1998). “Psychopathy and the contribution of personality to violence,” in Psychopathy: Antisocial, Criminal, and Violent Behavior, eds T. Millon, E. Simonsen, M. Birket-Smith, and R. D. Davis (New York, NY: Guilford Press), 50–68.

Blackburn, R., and Maybury, C. (1985). Identifying the psychopath: the relation of Cleckley's criteria to the interpersonal domain. Pers. Indiv. Differ. 6, 375–386.

Bowen, J., Teri, L., Kukull, W., McCormick, W., McCurry, S. M., and Larson, E. B. (1997). Progression to dementia in patients with isolated memory loss. Lancet 349, 763–765.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Buss, D. M., Haselton, M. G., Shackelford, T. K., Bleske, A. L., and Wakefield, J. C. (1998). Adaptations, exaptations, and spandrels. Am. Psychol. 53, 533–548.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Cannon, M., Jones, P. B., and Murray, R. M. (2002). Obstetric complications and schizophrenia: Historical and meta-analytic review. Am. J. Psychiatry 159, 1080–1092.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Corcoran, R., and Frith, C. D. (2003). Autobiographical memory and theory of mind: evidence of a relationship in schizophrenia. Psychol. Med. 33, 897–905.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Corr, P. J. (2010). The psychoticism-psychopathy continuum: a neuropsychological model of core deficits. Pers. Indiv. Differ. 48, 695–703.

Daly, M., and Wilson, M. (1982). Homicide and kinship. Am. Anthropol. 84, 372–378.

Daly, M., and Wilson, M. (1988a). Homicide. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter.

Daly, M., and Wilson, M. (1988b). Evolutionary social psychology and family homicide. Science 242, 519–524.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Daly, M., and Wilson, M. (2010). “Cultural inertia, economic incentives, and the persistence of ‘Southern violence’,” in Evolution, Culture, and the Human Mind, eds M. Schaller, A. Norenzayan, S. Heine, T. Yamagishi, and T. Kameda (New York, NY: Taylor and Francis), 229–241.

Daly, M., Wilson, M., and Weghorst, S. J. (1982). Male sexual jealousy. Ethol. Sociobiol. 3, 11–27.

Eysenck, H. J. (1992). The definition and measurement of psychoticism. Pers. Indiv. Differ. 13, 757–785.

Eysenck, H. J., and Eysenck, S. B. G. (1977). Psychoticism as a Dimension of Personality. Oxford: Crane and Russak.

Franks, N. R. (1985). Reproduction, foraging efficiency and worker polymorphism in army ants. Forts. Zool. 31, 91–107.

Franks, N. R. (1986). Teams in social insects: group retrieval of prey by army ants (Eciton burchelli, Hymenoptera: Formicidae). Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 18, 425–429.

Frith, C. D., and Done, D. J. (1989). Experiences of alien control in schizophrenia reflect a disorder in the central monitoring of action. Psychol. Med. 19, 359–363.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Fullam, R., and Dolan, M. (2006). The criminal and personality profile of patients with schizophrenia and comorbid psychopathic traits. Pers. Indiv. Differ. 40, 1591–1602.

Gould, S. J., and Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 205, 581–598.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Grafen, A. (2006). Optimization of inclusive fitness. J. Theor. Biol. 238, 541–563.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Gross, M. R. (1991). Evolution of alternative reproductive strategies: frequency-dependent sexual selection in male bluegill sunfish. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B 332, 59–66.

Gross, M. R., and Charnov, E. L. (1980). Alternative male life histories in bluegill sunfish. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 77, 6937–6940.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour (I and II). J. Theor. Biol. 7, 1–52.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hamilton, W. D. (1970). Selfish and spiteful behaviour in an evolutionary model. Nature 228, 1218–1220.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Hare, R. D. (1991). Manual for the Hare Psychopathy Checklist-Revised. Toronto, ON: Multi-Health Systems.

Hare, R. D. (1993). Without Conscience. New York, NY: Pocket Books.

Harpending, H. C., and Sobus, J. (1987). Sociopathy as an adaptation. Ethol. Sociobiol. 8(Supp. 1), 63–72.

Harris, G. T., Hilton, N. Z., Rice, M. E., and Eke, A. W. (2007a). Children killed by genetic parents versus stepparents. Evol. Hum. Behav. 28, 85–95.

Harris, G. T., Rice, M. E., Hilton, N. Z., Lalumière, M. L., and Quinsey, V. L. (2007b). Coercive and precocious sexuality as a fundamental aspect of psychopathy. J. Pers. Disord. 21, 1–27.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Harris, G. T., Rice, M. E., and Lalumière, M. (2001a). Criminal violence: the roles of psychopathy, neurodevelopmental insults, and antisocial parenting. Crim. Justice Behav. 28, 402–426.

Harris, G. T., Skilling, T. A., and Rice, M. E. (2001b). The construct of psychopathy. Crime Justice 28, 197–264.

Hughes, W. O. H., Oldroyd, B. P., Beekman, M., and Ratnieks, F. L. W. (2008). Ancestral monogamy shows kin selection is key to the evolution of eusociality. Science 320, 1213–1216.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Krupp, D. B., Sewall, L. A., Lalumière, M. L., Sheriff, C., and Harris, G. T. (2012). Nepotistic patterns of violent psychopathy: evidence for adaptation? Front. Psychol. 3:305. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00305

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Lalumière, M. L., Harris, G. T., and Rice, M. E. (2001). Psychopathy and developmental instability. Evol. Hum. Behav. 22, 75–92.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Lalumière, M. L., and Quinsey, V. L. (1996). Sexual deviance, antisociality, mating effort, and the use of sexually coercive behaviors. Pers. Indiv. Differ. 21, 33–48.

Leedom, L. J., and Hartoonian Almas, L. (2012). Is psychopathy a disorder or an adaptation? Front. Psychol. 3:549. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00549

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Markow, T. A. (1992). Genetics and developmental stability: an integrative conjecture on etiology and neurobiology of schizophrenia. Psychol. Med. 22, 295–305.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

McGregor, K., Castle, D., and Dolan, M. (2012). Schizophrenia spectrum disorders, substance misuse, and the four-facet model of psychopathy: the relationship to violence. Schizophr. Res. 136, 116–121.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mealey, L. (1995). The sociobiology of sociopathy: an integrated evolutionary model. Behav. Brain Sci. 18, 523–599.

Nathaniel-James, D. A., and Frith, C. D. (1996). Confabulation in schizophrenia: evidence of a new form? Psychol. Med. 26, 391–399.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Power, R. A., Kyaga, S., Uher, R., MacCabe, J. H., Långström, N., Landen, M., et al. (2013). Fecundity of patients with schizophrenia, autism, bipolar disorder, depression, anorexia nervosa, or substance abuse vs. their unaffected siblings. JAMA Psychiatry 70, 22–30.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Pulkkinen, L., Lyyra, A. L., and Kokko, K. (2009). Life success of males on nonoffender, adolescence-limited, persistent, and adult-onset antisocial pathways: follow-up from age 8 to 42. Aggress. Behav. 35, 117–135.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Quinsey, V. L., Rice, M. E., and Harris, G. T. (1995). Actuarial prediction of sexual recidivism. J. Interpers. Violence 10, 85–105.

Scoville, W. B., and Milner, B. (1957). Loss of recent memory after bilateral hippocampal lesions. J. Neurol. Neurosur. Psychiatry 20, 11–21.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Suchankova, P., Klang, J., Cavanna, C., Holm, G., Nilsson, S., Jonsson, E. G., et al. (2012). Is the Gly82Ser polymorphism in the RAGE gene relevant to schizophrenia and the personality trait psychoticism? J. Psychiatry Neurosci. 37, 122–128.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Vachon, D. D., Lynam, D. R., Loeber, R., and Stouthamer-Loeber, M. (2012). Generalizing the nomological network of psychopathy across populations differing on race and conviction status. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 121, 263–269.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder: on the boundary between biological facts and social values. Am. Psychol. 47, 373–388.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Weinberg, S. M., Jenkins, E. A., Marazita, M. L., and Maher, B. S. (2007). Minor physical anomalies in schizophrenia: a meta-analysis. Schizophr. Res. 89, 72–85.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wilson, M., and Daly, M. (1985). Competitiveness, risk taking, and violence: the young male syndrome. Ethol. Sociobiol. 6, 59–73.

Wilson, M., and Daly, M. (1993). Spousal homicide risk and estrangement. Violence Vict. 8, 3–16.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Wilson, M., and Daly, M. (1997). Life expectancy, economic inequality, homicide, and reproductive timing in Chicago neighbourhoods. BMJ 314, 1271–1274.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Wilson, M. I., and Daly, M. (1992). Who kills whom in spouse killings? On the exceptional sex ratio of spousal homicides in the United States. Criminology 30, 189–215.

Wilson, M. I., Daly, M., and Weghorst, S. J. (1980). Household composition and the risk of child abuse and neglect. J. Biosoc. Sci. 12, 333–340.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text

Keywords: psychopathy, mental disorder, adaptation, social evolution, inclusive fitness theory

Citation: Krupp DB, Sewall LA, Lalumière ML, Sheriff C and Harris GT (2013) Psychopathy, adaptation, and disorder. Front. Psychol. 4:139. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00139

Received: 16 February 2013; Accepted: 04 March 2013;
Published online: 27 March 2013.

Edited by:

Ed Hagen, Washington State University, USA

Reviewed by:

Ed Hagen, Washington State University, USA

Copyright © 2013 Krupp, Sewall, Lalumière, Sheriff and Harris. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in other forums, provided the original authors and source are credited and subject to any copyright notices concerning any third-party graphics etc.

*Correspondence: Daniel Brian Krupp, Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Queen's University, Jeffery Hall, Kingston, ON K7L 3N6, Canada. e-mail: daniel.krupp@queensu.ca

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.