Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 24 September 2013
Sec. Psychology of Language

Neanderthal language? Just-so stories take center stage

  • 1Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science/Brain and Cognitive Sciences, Laboratory for Information and Decision Systems, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA, USA
  • 2Risk-Eraser, LLC, Falmouth, MA, USA
  • 3Division of Anthropology, American Museum of Natural History, New York, NY, USA

A commentary on
On the antiquity of language: the reinterpretation of Neandertal linguistic capacities and its consequences

by Dediu, D., and Levinson, S. (2013). Front. Psychol. 4:397. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00397

Dediu and Levinson (2013) link two extraordinary claims: first, humans and Neanderthals were one and the same species and second, “Speech and language … are ancient, being present in a modern-like form over half a million years ago in the common ancestor of Neanderthals and modern humans, the result of evolution in the prior one million years or so as H. heidelbergensis evolved from H. erectus” (p. 12). These claims are marred by their selective review of the literature; the use of equivocal evidence as definitive support for their interpretation; and the lack of any evolutionary evidence regarding the computations and representations that mediate modern linguistic competence.

Our language phenotype is a competence consisting of three systems—syntax, semantics, and phonology—that are internal to the mind/brain, along with two mediating interfaces, the first linking the representational/computational systems to external speech or sign, the second linking language to internal thought. The internal combinatorial computations are generative and rule-governed, engaging representations that are both language-specific and domain-general. Generalized claims such as Dediu and Levinson's require evidence for all of these processes. But most of them do not leave fossil evidence; and genetic clarification is unlikely given how poorly we understand simpler phentoypes. For example, though language is expressed through articulate speech today, the anatomical capacity for speech cannot by itself be taken as a proxy for language. The peripheral organs have to connect with the internal phonological, syntactic and semantic representations, and nothing in the fossil record is ever likely to tell us: (a) what those representations were like; or (b) whether the human brain had yet formed the necessary connections between, e.g., phonological representations and vocal output. This does not bode well for the type of argument Dediu and Levinson advance, but let us examine the evidence they present.

Dediu and Levinson never describe the language phenotype, except to note that it is the “full suite of abilities to map sounds to meaning” (p. 2). Because the phenotype is not specified at the required level of detail for evolutionary analysis, it is difficult to test their evolutionary claims. But this lack of detail does permit them to assert that language competence was likely among Neanderthals, due to nothing more than their large brains, cognitive complexity, and proclaimed conspecificity with modern humans. Still, hominids can be smart without implying modern cognition (Tattersall, 2012), and smart does not necessarily mean that Neanderthals had the competence for language or the capacity to externalize it in speech. Further, while Dediu and Levinson rely on recent reports of low-level genetic interchange between Homo neanderthalensis and Homo sapiens as evidence of conspecificity, minor gene flow is to be expected between closely related sympatric species (Coyne and Orr, 2004; Mallet, 2005), and anatomical and genetic analyses reveal that both lineages were morphologically and historically individuated (Tattersall and Schwartz, 2006; Currat and Excoffier, 2011). Their argument additionally rests on the implicit claim that limited interbreeding among these hominids, with resulting genetic admixture, actually yielded specific genetic differences in African vs. non-African human populations that led to specifically different phenotypic language traits. But no evidence is provided in support of this claim.

Dediu and Levinson assert that unambiguous symbolic behavior among the Neanderthals/Denisovans provides evidence of language competence. There are two grave problems with this claim: symbolic behavior, as in cave painting, is an indirect proxy for language, and its earliest indications come from Homo sapiens, not Neanderthals, and only at sites dated at roughly 100 kyr or less [e.g., 77-kyr engraved ochres from Blombos Cave, South Africa; (Henshilwood et al., 2009)]. Archaeology thus supports a recent timeframe for the emergence of modern behaviors associated with language: substantially after the emergence of Homo sapiens at ca. 200 kyr. But even this evidence is silent on semantic representations, links to syntax and phonology, and so on. Thus, even if all of their supposed evidence were germane and correct, it would not suffice to demonstrate that either Neanderthals—or even the first Homo sapiens—had modern language competence, or the capacity to externalize it in speech.

Along with the (expected) genomic similarity among Neanderthals, Denisovans and modern humans, Dediu and Levinson present several gene-level commonalities as evidence for Neanderthal genomic compatibility with language, e.g., FOXP2. Again, the analysis is highly selective. FOXP2 is only one of many genes contributing to articulate speech. It has little to do with the central control of language, but is rather involved with its externalization. Neither Neanderthals nor Denisovans possessed human variants of other putatively “language-related” alleles such as CNTAP2, ASPM, and MCPH1 (Microcephalin), among others, so the evidence is actually equivocal. The survey they themselves cite (Somel et al., 2013) arrives at a different conclusion: “There is accumulating evidence that human brain development was fundamentally reshaped through several genetic events within the short time space between the human-Neandertal split and the emergence of modern humans” (Somel et al., 2013, p.119, our emph.). In any event, it is currently unknown how genetic variants build language competence in modern humans, let alone in Neanderthals.

Dediu and Levinson conclude that (1) “saltationist” stories for language origin must be rejected; (2) language evolved incrementally; (3) gene-culture interaction greatly affected language's “design”; (4) a “deeper” historical linguistics is called for; and (5) modern human languages might not reflect the full space of language possibilities. All this is speculative to the point of irrelevance. (1) is contradicted both by the modern understanding of evolutionary patterns (Thompson, 2013) and by empirical evidence that hominid evolution is best characterized by long periods of stasis interspersed with more rapid changes (Tattersall, 2012); no evidence whatsoever is brought forward to support (2); (3) and (4) are directly contradicted both by the rapidity of gene-culture co-evolution that they themselves embrace (Baronchelli et al., 2012) and also by psycholinguistic findings (Wong et al., 2012); and (5) is contradicted by evidence that the space of possible phonological and syntactic variation has not really changed in the past 10 kyr—Ancient Sumerian looks just like any other contemporary human language.

In short, Dediu and Levinson's extraordinary claims are not supported by the evidence they present. More significantly, we doubt that there could be any evidence to support such claims. At the archaeological level, our core linguistic competence does not fossilize. As for molecular evidence, we are nowhere near identifying the relevant “language genotype” and they provide no “language phenotype” to guide us. For the present, abstinence from speculation may be the best remedy.

Author contributions

Robert C. Berwick, Marc D. Hauser, and Ian Tattersall contributed equally to the writing of this commentary.

References

Baronchelli, A., Chater, N., Pastor-Satorras, R., and Christiansen, M. (2012). The biological origin of linguistic diversity. PLoS ONE 7:e48029. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0048029

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Coyne, J., and Orr, A. (2004). Speciation. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.

Currat, M., and Excoffier, L. (2011). Strong reproductive isolation between humans and Neandertals inferred from observed patterns of introgression. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 15129–15134. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1107450108

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Dediu, D., and Levinson, S. (2013). On the antiquity of language: the reinterpretation of Neandertal linguistic capacities and its consequences. Front. Psychol. 4:397. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00397

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Henshilwood, C., d'Errico, F., and Watts, I. (2009). Engraved ochres from the middle stone age levels at Blombos Cave, South Africa. J. Hum. Evol. 57, 27–47. doi: 10.1016/j.jhevol.2009.01.005

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mallet, J. (2005). Hybridization as an invasion of the genome. Trends Ecol. Evol. 20, 229–237. doi: 10.1016/j.tree.2005.02.010

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Somel, M., Liu, X., and Khaitovich, P. (2013). Human brain evolution: transcripts, metabolites and their regulators. Nat. Rev. Neurosci.14, 112–127. doi: 10.1038/nrn3372

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Tattersall, I. (2012). Masters of the Planet: the Search for our Human Origins. New York, NY: Palgrave-MacMillan.

Tattersall, I., and Schwartz, J. H. (2006). “The distinctiveness and systematic context of Homo neanderthalensis,” in Neanderthals Revisited: New Approaches and Perspectives, eds Harvati, K., Harrison, T. (Berlin; New York: Springer), 9–22.

Thompson, R. (2013). Relentless Evolution. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. doi: 10.7208/chicago/9780226018898.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text

Wong, P. C. M., Chandrasekaran, B., and Zheng, J. (2012). The derived allele of ASPM is associated with lexical tone perception. PLoS ONE 7:e34243. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0034243

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: language evolution, human evolution, language contact, genetic admixture

Citation: Berwick RC, Hauser MD and Tattersall I (2013) Neanderthal language? Just-so stories take center stage. Front. Psychol. 4:671. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00671

Received: 29 August 2013; Accepted: 06 September 2013;
Published online: 24 September 2013.

Edited by:

Sonja A. E. Kotz, Max Planck Institute Leipzig, Germany

Reviewed by:

Sonja A. E. Kotz, Max Planck Institute Leipzig, Germany

Copyright © 2013 Berwick, Hauser and Tattersall. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: berwick@csail.mit.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.