Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 19 May 2016
Sec. Perception Science
This article is part of the Research Topic How Variable, Stable, or Universal are Aesthetic Preferences? View all 22 articles

Individual Differences in Aesthetic Ability: The Case for an Aesthetic Quotient

  • 1Department of Psychology, Pace University, New York, NY, USA
  • 2Laboratoire Adaptations Travail-Individu, Université Paris Descartes - Sorbonne Paris Cité, Paris, France

Although the reasons individuals have specific stable aesthetic preferences—for example, for abstract art or for classical music—are often studied (e.g., Furnham and Walker, 2001), there is a growing stream of research (e.g., Nodine et al., 1993; Chamorro-Premuzic and Furnham, 2004; Axelsson, 2007; Kozbelt and Seeley, 2007; Silvia, 2007; Myszkowski et al., 2014) that is interested in the various abilities involved when evaluating art: Are we all equally “armed” to process aesthetic stimuli?

Our aim in this paper is to propose a new direction for this stream of research. While a typical approach to the study of aesthetic ability consists in measuring single facets, notably aesthetic sensitivity (e.g., Myszkowski et al., 2014), we propose a multi-content approach. More specifically, mirroring the “g-to-IQ” shift in intelligence measurement, we want to propose a “T-to-AQ” shift from single-content measures of “good taste” (“T”) to comprehensive assessments of an “Aesthetic Quotient” (AQ), which would include other facets of aesthetic ability—like artistic knowledge, sensitivity to complexity and aesthetic empathy. Rather that questioning the existence of an AQ, we argue its usefulness, notably in predicting creative potential and achievement.

A Central “T” Construct

What we propose as a central construct to aesthetic ability has gone by many names—“Aesthetic Judgment” (Meier, 1940; Graves, 1948), “Aesthetic Perception” (Meier, 1963) or “Aesthetic Sensitivity” (Götz, 1985)—but it is commonly referred to as “T” for “Taste” (Eysenck, 1983; Myszkowski et al., 2014), which embraces the most clearly its definition: It is the ability to respond to aesthetic stimuli in agreement with ≪external standards≫ (Child, 1964). In other words, “T” is the ability to judge “well”—which, practically speaking, means “consensus-like” and/or “expert-like” (Myszkowski et al., 2014).

Although the letter “T” refers to Taste, it is important to note that “T” actually does not refer to personal taste (or personal preferences), but rather to the concept of “good taste”—“good” referring to relevant, appropriate or correct—as we commonly use it to describe individual characteristics. “T” is a specific ability involved in aesthetic experience (Myszkowski et al., 2014), which is a broader concept that refers to the entire activity relative to the processing of aesthetic stimuli (Leder et al., 2004).

Evidence for “T”

It is interesting to note here that such a letter-sobriquet—originally proposed by Eysenck (1940)—is a direct reference to the general factor of intelligence, g. While Eysenck's provocative personality probably played a role in doing such a comparison, the “T” factor was indeed the result of the extraction—using exploratory factor analysis—of a principal component of aesthetic personal preferences, a lot like g was the result of the extraction of a principal component of intelligence test scores. Individuals tend to agree on the preference for aesthetic stimuli in most visual domains (Eysenck, 1940)—thus, consensual preferences exist for most stimuli—and the judges who tend to agree with average judgments are the same individuals for a wide variety of visual domains (Eysenck, 1940, 1941a)—therefore, individuals who agree with consensual preferences do so in a wide variety kinds of stimuli. These results point to a factor of individual differences that is stable across visual domains, and that corresponds to the extent to which our judgments are in agreement with consensually established standards.

Measuring “T”

But measuring “T” is a challenge: How do we know if an individual responds to stimuli in accordance to “external standards”? How can we define “external standards”? The way that “T” has been discovered by Eysenck points to a clear way of addressing this issue: We identify or build pairs (or triads) of stimuli, so that one is preferred (by consensual agreement and experts) over one (or two) deteriorated versions of it. The aim of this first step is to build pairs or triads of designs, which each include a design of higher “objective” aesthetic quality than the others. These pairs or triads are then used as items: The test takers are asked to indicate, for each pair or triad, which of the two (or three) designs they consider of better objective quality (Meier, 1940, 1963; Graves, 1948; Götz, 1985; Myszkowski et al., 2014). A better “T” score is attributed to individuals who are better able to effectively recognize the stimuli that are aesthetically superior.

Integrating Connected Constructs

The Lack of a Pure “T” Measure

Among what were designed as pure “T” measures, the Design Judgment Test (Graves, 1948) and the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test (Götz, 1985) have been, because of their psychometrical qualities, the most heavily used (Chamorro-Premuzic and Furnham, 2004; Furnham and Chamorro-Premuzic, 2004; Myszkowski et al., 2014; Summerfeldt et al., 2015). However, “T” measures are restricted by their content (Gear, 1986). More specifically, when building these measures, researchers have built items that are not representative of the entire visual domain, and we could point to many signs of this lack of representativeness—the stimuli of these tests are mostly black and white (or black, gray and white) paintings (Götz, 1985). Consequently, these measures have been severely criticized as not being representative of “T.” Gear (1986, pp. 563–564), for example, sarcastically described the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test as “a test of the ability to discriminate between greater and lesser degrees of ‘harmony’ in monochromatic two-dimensional figures in the same way as the well-known German painter Götz, eight other well-known painters and the well-known British psychologist Professor H. J. Eysenck.”

“T” is to aesthetic ability what g is to mental ability: Central, but difficult—if not impossible—to measure with a single test. However, while intelligence researchers switched from appreciated attempts to build pure “g” measures (Raven, 1941)—which are still not measures of pure intelligence (Gignac, 2015)—to comprehensive multifactorial IQ test batteries (e.g., Wechsler, 2008), this hasn't been the case for aesthetic ability, which hasn't evolved from “T” to AQ.

Other AQ Components

While measures that were designed to measure purely “T” may have failed in completely isolating it, it can be argued that these few measures are not the only tools that are available to capture aesthetic ability. The concept of aesthetic ability is multifaceted, and the measure of aesthetic ability should thus probably not be restricted to making aesthetic judgments of monochromatic paintings.

There is a set of existing constructs and measures that could be used in a comprehensive AQ assessment. We could propose for example the sensitivity to complex stimuli—named “K” in reference to the use of K for complexity in mathematics (Eysenck, 1941b)—which is already investigated in the field of creativity research, through the Figure-Preference Test (Barron and Welsh, 1952), and largely used to in the study of the creative personality (Eysenck and Furnham, 1993). We could also consider as an AQ component art knowledge, currently measured with the Aesthetic Fluency scale (Smith and Smith, 2006; Silvia, 2007) or the Aesthetic Experience Questionnaire (Chatterjee et al., 2010). Additionally, measures of aesthetic empathy (Lifton, 1961; Madsen et al., 1993; McCrae, 2007; Silvia and Nusbaum, 2011), or of the diversity of exploration patterns (Nodine et al., 1993) could be useful additions to a more comprehensive study of aesthetic ability.

Indeed, we here argue that various sources of individual differences—sensitivity to complexity, art knowledge, aesthetic empathy, attention, exploratory perception tendencies—constitute elements that make individuals more armed to process art and aesthetic stimuli, making them suitable candidates for inclusion in potential AQ assessment. However, this list is non-exhaustive and some of the existing measures (content, norms, scoring) would need to be updated before inclusion in a test battery. In Figure 1, we summarize our AQ approach. Because of their extensiveness in the visual domain, we propose example measures for each of the facets in this domain. We however think that similar measures should be found in other domains: For example, a pitch recognition test could be considered as measure of aesthetic balance recognition in the musical domain. Associated with the list of components that we propose, we could tentatively define AQ as the global capacity to identify, explore, understand, seek stimulation in and respond to the elements, composition and meaning of art and aesthetic objects.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Model for an Aesthetic Quotient approach of “T.”.

Why Measure Aesthetic Ability?

AQ is Useful

The case has been previously made (e.g., Eysenck, 1988) that the existence of intelligence is not what is demonstrated by the discovery of g, but that such a discovery indicates a factor that is useful to explain and understand scores in mental ability tests, as well as to predict a variety of outcomes, like academic achievement. Making an analogous point for AQ, we acknowledge that the idea that aesthetic judgments can be of better or worse quality—and that, consequently, individuals capable of making better judgments have better taste—is a fascinating philosophical question, but we are not here positing that good taste exists: We are arguing, as it was suggested about “T” (Myszkowski et al., in press), that AQ is useful as a scientific concept, notably in the prediction and explanation of creativity.

While AQ concerns the “reception end” of aesthetic stimuli, it may be useful in the prediction of the “production end”: Creativity. Indeed, results suggest that the AQ components that we discussed earlier are helpful to predict a variety of outcomes that are creativity related. First, let us note that recent research has indicated that the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test is a significant predictor of creative potential (Myszkowski et al., 2014). This suggests that individuals who are better equipped to judge aesthetic stimuli can probably use these tools to create. Additionally, the Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test and the Design Judgment Test were found to be related to creative personality traits like openness to aesthetics (Myszkowski et al., 2014). Besides, other AQ components that we proposed are also predictors of creativity. For example, aesthetic response intensity was found to be related to creative potential (Ziv and Keydar, 2009). Moreover, research indicates that artists have higher art expertise and process aesthetic stimuli differently (Kozbelt and Seeley, 2007). For example, photo professionals process photographic information more efficiently and prefer complex photos (Axelsson, 2007).

These results suggest that aesthetic sensitivity could be partly related to the development of creativity. To give examples of concrete applications, one could imagine that a designer's ability to create a highly ergonomic and efficient webpage design could be predicted by aesthetic ability. One could also propose training programs, using exploratory art perception activities, to enhance AQ among children or adults.

Conclusion

We have here proposed the evolution of “T” toward a more comprehensive “AQ” approach and assessment of aesthetic ability. First, we have discussed the concept of “T” as a central factor of individual differences in the ability to judge aesthetic stimuli, and explained that results show that it is rather stable across a variety of categories of stimuli of a specific domain. We however noted that supposedly pure “T” measures have failed in fully encompassing aesthetic ability. We later proposed an evolution in the study of aesthetic ability, from attempting to purely measure “T” to a more comprehensive approach. We have proposed for this approach the term Aesthetic Quotient (AQ), as a reference to the “g-to-IQ” shift to comprehensive assessments of intelligence (e.g., Wechsler, 2008). We finally explained that psychology and empirical aesthetics researchers should probably stay clear of philosophical debates on the existence of aesthetic ability, and rather focus on the accumulating evidence on the usefulness of AQ components as predictors of creative potential and achievement.

Author Contributions

NM's contribution has consisted in conceiving the paper, drafting and revising the paper and the figure. FZ contributed substantially in the conception of the paper, and in critically improving the manuscript and enhancing its quality for publication.

Funding

This article was supported by grant RFP-15-05 from the Imagination Institute (www.imagination-institute.org), funded by the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the view of the Imagination Institute or the John Templeton Foundation.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Axelsson, Ö. (2007). Individual differences in preferences to photographs. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 1, 61–72. doi: 10.1037/1931-3896.1.2.61

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barron, F., and Welsh, G. S. (1952). Artistic perception as a possible factor in personality style: its measurement by a figure preference test. J. Psychol. 33, 199–203. doi: 10.1080/00223980.1952.9712830

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chamorro-Premuzic, T., and Furnham, A. (2004). Art judgment: a measure related to both personality and intelligence? Imag. Cogn. Pers. 24, 3–24. doi: 10.2190/U4LW-TH9X-80M3-NJ54

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chatterjee, A., Widick, P., Sternschein, R., Smith, W. B., and Bromberger, B. (2010). The assessment of art attributes. Empir. Stud. Arts 28, 207–222. doi: 10.2190/EM.28.2.f

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Child, I. L. (1964). Observations on the meaning of some measures of esthetic sensitivity. J. Psychol. 57, 49–64. doi: 10.1080/00223980.1964.9916671

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J. (1940). The general factor in aesthetic judgements. Br. J. Psychol. Gen. Sect. 31, 94–102. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1940.tb00977.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J. (1941a). The empirical determination of an aesthetic formula. Psychol. Rev. 48, 83–92. doi: 10.1037/h0062483

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J. (1941b). “Type” factors in aesthetic judgements. Br. J. Psychol. Gen. Sect. 31, 262–270. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1941.tb00992.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J. (1983). A new measure of “good taste” in visual art. Leonardo 16, 229. doi: 10.2307/1574921

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J. (1988). The concept of “intelligence”: useful or useless? Intelligence 12, 1–16. doi: 10.1016/j.diagmicrobio.2016.03.021

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eysenck, H. J., and Furnham, A. (1993). Personality and the barron-welsh art scale. Percept. Mot. Skills 76, 837–838. doi: 10.2466/pms.1993.76.3.837

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Furnham, A., and Chamorro-Premuzic, T. (2004). Personality, intelligence, and art. Pers. Individ. Diff. 36, 705–715. doi: 10.1016/S0191-8869(03)00128-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Furnham, A., and Walker, J. (2001). Personality and judgements of abstract, pop art, and representational paintings. Eur. J. Pers. 15, 57–72. doi: 10.1002/per.340

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gear, J. (1986). Eysenck's visual aesthetic sensitivity test (VAST) as an example of the need for explicitness and awareness of context in empirical aesthetics. Poetics 15, 555–564. doi: 10.1016/0304-422X(86)90011-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gignac, G. E. (2015). Raven's is not a pure measure of general intelligence: Implications for g factor theory and the brief measurement of g. Intelligence 52, 71–79. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2788.2008.01045.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Götz, K. O. (1985). VAST: Visual Aesthetic Sensitivity Test, 4th Edn. Dusseldorf: Concept Verlag.

Graves, M. E. (1948). Design Judgment Test. New York, NY: Psychological Corporation.

Kozbelt, A., and Seeley, W. P. (2007). Integrating art historical, psychological, and neuroscientific explanations of artists' advantages in drawing and perception. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 1, 80–90. doi: 10.1037/1931-3896.1.2.80

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leder, H., Belke, B., Oeberst, A., and Augustin, D. (2004). A model of aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic judgments. Br. J. Psychol. 95, 489–508. doi: 10.1348/0007126042369811

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lifton, W. M. (1961). The development of a music reaction test to measure affective and aesthetic sensitivity. J. Res. Music Educ. 9, 157–166. doi: 10.2307/3344311

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Madsen, C. K., Brittin, R. V., and Capperella-Sheldon, D. A. (1993). An empirical method for measuring the aesthetic experience to music. J. Res. Music Educ. 41, 57–69. doi: 10.2307/3345480

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McCrae, R. R. (2007). Aesthetic chills as a universal marker of openness to experience. Motiv. Emotion 31, 5–11. doi: 10.1007/s11031-007-9053-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meier, N. C. (1940). The Meier Art Tests: I, Art Judgment. Iowa City, IA: Bureau of Educational Research and Service, University of Iowa.

Meier, N. C. (1963). The Meier Art Tests: II, Aesthetic Perception. Iowa City, IA: Bureau of Educational Research and Service, University of Iowa.

Myszkowski, N., Storme, M., and Zenasni, F. (in press). Order in complexity: how hans eysenck brought differential psychology aesthetics together. Pers. Individ. Diff.

Myszkowski, N., Storme, M., Zenasni, F., and Lubart, T. (2014). Is visual aesthetic sensitivity independent from intelligence, personality and creativity? Pers. Individ. Dif. 59, 16–20. doi: 10.1016/j.paid.2013.10.021

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nodine, C. F., Locher, P. J., and Krupinski, E. A. (1993). The role of formal art training on perception and aesthetic judgment of art compositions. Leonardo 26, 219. doi: 10.2307/1575815

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Raven, J. C. (1941). Standardization of progressive matrices, 1938. Br. J. Med. Psychol. 19, 137–150. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8341.1941.tb00316.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Silvia, P. J. (2007). Knowledge-based assessment of expertise in the arts: Exploring aesthetic fluency. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 1, 247–249. doi: 10.1037/1931-3896.1.4.247

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Silvia, P. J., and Nusbaum, E. C. (2011). On personality and piloerection: Individual differences in aesthetic chills and other unusual aesthetic experiences. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 5, 208–214. doi: 10.1037/a0021914

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, L. F., and Smith, J. K. (2006). The nature and growth of aesthetic fluency, in New Directions in Aesthetics, Creativity and the Arts eds P. Locher, C. Martindale, and L. Dorfman (Amityville, NY: Baywood Publishing Co), 47–58.

Summerfeldt, L. J., Gilbert, S. J., and Reynolds, M. (2015). Incompleteness, aesthetic sensitivity, and the obsessive-compulsive need for symmetry. J. Behav. Ther. Exp. Psychiatry 49, 141–149. doi: 10.1016/j.jbtep.2015.03.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wechsler, D. (2008). Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale, 4th Ed (WAIS–IV). San Antonio, TX: NCS Pearson.

Google Scholar

Ziv, N., and Keydar, E. (2009). The relationship between creative potential, aesthetic response to music, and musical preferences. Creat. Res. J. 21, 125–133. doi: 10.1080/10400410802633764

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: aesthetic judgment, aesthetic appreciation, creativity, empirical aesthetics, aesthetic preference

Citation: Myszkowski N and Zenasni F (2016) Individual Differences in Aesthetic Ability: The Case for an Aesthetic Quotient. Front. Psychol. 7:750. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00750

Received: 29 February 2016; Accepted: 06 May 2016;
Published: 19 May 2016.

Edited by:

Edward A. Vessel, Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, Germany

Reviewed by:

Aaron Kozbelt, Brooklyn College and the Graduate Center of the City University of New York, USA

Copyright © 2016 Myszkowski and Zenasni. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Nils Myszkowski, nilsmyszkowski@yahoo.fr

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.