Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 04 January 2017
Sec. Cognition

Cross-Representational Interactions: Interface and Overlap Mechanisms

  • 1Department of Psychology, Northumbria University, Newcastle-upon-Tyne, UK
  • 2Centre for Cognition and Decision Making, National Research University Higher School of Economics, Moscow, Russia
  • 3Department of Psychology, Northumbria University, Newcastle-upon-Tyne, UK
  • 4Division of Cognitive Science, University of Potsdam, Potsdam, Germany

A crucial question facing cognitive science concerns the nature of conceptual representations as well as the constraints on the interactions between them. One specific question we address in this paper is what makes cross-representational interplay possible? We offer two distinct theoretical scenarios: according to the first scenario, co-activated knowledge representations interact with the help of an interface established between them via congruent activation in a mediating third-party general cognitive mechanism, e.g., attention. According to the second scenario, co-activated knowledge representations interact due to an overlap between their features, for example when they share a magnitude component. First, we make a case for cross-representational interplay based on grounded and situated theories of cognition. Second, we discuss interface-based interactions between distinct (i.e., non-overlapping) knowledge representations. Third, we discuss how co-activated representations may share their architecture via partial overlap. Finally, we outline constraints regarding the flexibility of these proposed mechanisms.

A strongly debated topic in cognitive science concerns whether or not sensorimotor information forms a necessary part of semantic representation (Barsalou, 2008; Lewandowsky, 2016; and linked contributions there). Conventional theories of cognition view the modal systems of perception and action independent of the amodal systems of semantic memory. Modal activations, therefore, are proposed to be transcoded into amodal symbols that translate experience into conceptual knowledge by means of abstracting away from sensory or motor activations (Fodor, 1983; Mahon and Caramazza, 2008; Mahon, 2015). One important consequence of this view is that both online (or temporarily established) and offline (core, or permanently stored) representations should not reveal modal features that reflect embodied experience, e.g., traces of sensorimotor activations.

A counterargument to this modular view is offered by embodied, grounded, or situated approaches to cognition, suggesting instead that conceptual knowledge is tightly integrated with the modal systems (Barsalou, 1999; Pulvermüller, 1999; Vigliocco et al., 2004; Myachykov et al., 2014). In this view, sensorimotor experiences form a constitutive part of semantic knowledge. While the debate continues (cf. Meteyard et al., 2012), here we follow embodied theories and discuss cognition as simulation, or “the re-enactment of perceptual, motor, and introspective states acquired during experience with the world, body, and mind” (Barsalou, 2009, p. 1281). This approach allows us to advance specific hypotheses regarding (1) offline and online properties of co-activated conceptual representations as well as (2) the diagnostic features for the distinct interactive contexts.

Recent research into the cognitive representations of apparently abstract1 concepts is consistent with embodied approach: for example, representations of the concepts denoting emotional valence (Foroni and Semin, 2009), time (Bottini et al., 2015), and number (Myachykov et al., 2016) were shown to be intimately linked with the perceptual experiences associated with their acquisition and use. Supporting this claim, several studies demonstrated that regular spatial-conceptual mappings accompany processing of words or symbols with numerical (Fischer, 2003; Fischer et al., 2004), spatial (Richardson et al., 2003), emotional (Meier and Robinson, 2004), and temporal (Núñez and Cooperrider, 2013) semantics. For example, people map positive emotions onto upper space and negative emotions onto lower space (e.g., Meier and Robinson, 2004). Similarly, in the temporal domain, the past is associated with left space and the future – with right space (Núñez and Cooperrider, 2013). Finally, in the number domain, small magnitudes map onto left space and large magnitudes – onto right space (Fischer and Shaki, 2014, for review).

These and similar spatial associations provide evidence for the role of sensorimotor systems in activation of single concepts (i.e., numbers, space, valence, and time). However, given the complexity and richness of the sensorimotor contexts that typically accompany cognitive processes and the pervasive involvement of modal systems in abstract thought, it is plausible to assume that co-activated concepts stemming from distinct knowledge domains would also rely on embodied principles in their interactions – either by means of a shared general cognitive mechanism or by sharing aspects of their mental representations. Below, we offer a brief sketch of a theoretical account that describes a dual-route proposal for cross-representational interactions. Specifically, we argue that co-activated representations interact either via an online interface established by a general cognitive system (e.g., attention or memory) or by means of a more permanent representational overlap; that is, by virtue of two or more representations sharing parts of their core architecture (e.g., magnitude, affect, or sequencing).

Theories of knowledge often define “conceptual representation” as a combination of its core (or permanent) and situated (or online) features (Wilson, 2002; Myachykov et al., 2014). This distinction is important for our argument: we propose that interface-based interactions are limited to online or situated contexts while overlap between representations is a feature of permanently stored representations. Although, it is notoriously difficult to trace offline their offline features, one can document the differences between different online renditions of the same offline representation. This can be illustrated with the set effect in Dehaene et al. (1993, Experiment 3): while offline representations for numbers 4 or 5 may be insensitive to any spatial-numerical mappings, their activation is accompanied by different situated spatial mappings depending on the set, within which they are activated. Namely, 4 and 5 show rightward mapping, associated with larger numbers, when activated in the set 0–5 and leftward mapping, typical for small numbers, – when activated in the set 4–9. In other words, while horizontality may be an off-line feature for both 4 and 5 its exact online displacement can be either left- or right-orienting (cf. Chiou et al., 2009 for another example of a similarly flexible mapping mechanism).

Representational Interface: Interactions Between (Relatively) Unrelated Representations

When two conceptual representations become co-activated, they may interact even if their individual architectures share little common ground. This interaction is supported by simultaneously engaging a third party component that acts as a mediator, or an interface (Figure 1A). As noted above, consistent spatial conceptual mappings have been documented for several distinct knowledge domains (e.g., Cappelletti et al., 2009; Holmes and Lourenco, 2011; Bonato et al., 2012; Hayashi et al., 2013; Lachmair et al., 2014b; Santiago and Lakens, 2015; Winter et al., 2015). Importantly, these and similar findings are not epiphenomenal: systematic and largely automatic shifts of covert spatial attention were shown to accompany these spatial-conceptual mappings, leading to cross-domain priming and thereby indicating functional benefits of establishing the interface. This is typically done by using secondary tasks that accompany processing of apparently abstract concepts (e.g., visual probe detection tasks) co-occurring with or following, a word processing task (e.g., Richardson et al., 2003). We hypothesize that, when co-activated, concepts known to carry similar spatial mappings regularly interface via a shared attentional system, thereby leading to more efficient sensorimotor mappings (cf. also Rizzolatti et al., 1994).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 1. (A) Interface and (B) overlap interactions in co-activated representations.

Although, there is a distinct lack of studies investigating the role of attention in cross-representational interplay, a number of existing reports provide initial evidence supporting our claim. For example, in experiments described in Lachmair et al. (2014a,b) participants were faster to signal lexical decisions for upward-orienting nouns (e.g., sun) or verbs (e.g., rise) following upward-orienting number prime (e.g., 9). According to the interface scenario proposed here, this priming effect reflects activation of the attentional interface shared by the two distinct conceptual representations. In effect, activation of the first stimulus (the number) established a cue (Posner, 1980) biasing attention toward the upper space. Because the subsequently presented word also has the capacity to cue attention toward upper space, its processing was facilitated.

We followed a similar logic in our recent experiments where we presented participants with a task requiring them to process two different concepts simultaneously (Chapman et al., in preparation). Participants read an upward or downward orienting valence word (e.g., hero/villain) followed by an upward or downward orienting number (e.g., 1/9). This sequence was followed by the presentation of a spatially congruent or incongruent visual probe, for which participants provided manual RTs. Hence, the probe could be either fully or partially (in)congruent to the word’s and number’s biases. Crucially, participants had to maintain both the word and the number in their working memory at the point of the probe detection task as they were later asked about either the identity of the word or the number. Performance on the visual probe detection task, seemingly unrelated to either of the two co-activated representations, showed interaction between words’ and numbers’ spatial biases similar to the one observed in Lachmair et al. (2014a,b).

Together, these studies provide initial evidence for the role of the same attentional mechanism in supporting cross-representational interactions. These studies also lend support to the idea that (1) the attentional system underlying spatial biases in apparently abstract knowledge representations is relatively general and universal and (2) that any two simultaneously accessed representations that are known to induce spatial biases can interact via the shared attentional system (e.g., Posner and Fan, 2008).

The most important diagnostic criterion for interface-based cross-representational interactions is that the mediator or interface does not feature as a semantic component of the interacting concepts’ meanings. Assume that the word hero and the number 9 are interfaced by sharing the upward attentional bias. While their co-activation would be measurable as a consistent attentional shift, neither of these two concepts represents vertical attention as a feature of its core meaning. This diagnostic feature stems from the constraint on when an interface can be established. We argue that interface-based interactions are limited to online contexts within which two concepts appear in temporal or spatial contiguity. Stored representations by themselves do not make reference to this interface system.

Spatial biases and attention are arguably the most studied general cognitive mechanisms supporting situated representations. As a result, we use attention as the “showcase” for our interface proposal. It is, however, not the only candidate for the role of an interface. Under our proposal, working memory can also act as an interface allowing cross-representational interactions (cf. Barsalou, 2008). While traditional conceptualizations of working memory propose distinct mechanisms for activation of verbal and visuospatial content (Baddeley, 1986), current views postulate that the active components of long-term knowledge representations constitute the equivalent of “working memory” (Cowan, 2005) and thus support cross-domain interfacing. An example could be the current debate about the origin of spatial-numerical associations, where sequential ordering of concepts might lead to spatial biases (for review, Abrahamse et al., 2016). Generally speaking, we predict that two co-activated representations that (1) share activation context (relational memory) or (2) have a comparable activation status – will interact.

Representational Overlap: Interactions Between Partially Related Representations

When co-activated representations are related via a shared architecture then such representations can interact by simultaneously activating the feature(s) that they share permanently, instead of looking for an interface as described above (e.g., Brunel et al., 2009; Rey et al., 2015; Riou et al., 2015). In comparison to the interface logic, (1) overlapping concepts simultaneously represent the overlapping feature as an integral semantic component and, as a result, (2) the overlap is pertinent for both online and off-line contexts. One instance of such overlap-based interaction occurs between the size (volume) of an afforded hand grip and the size (magnitude) of a numerical concept. Indeed, several studies confirmed that participant respond faster when the perceived object’s size corresponds to the perceived number’s magnitude (e.g., Andres et al., 2004, 2008; Lindemann et al., 2007; Moretto and Di Pellegrino, 2008; Ranzini et al., 2011, Gianelli et al., 2012; Namdar et al., 2014; Ranzini et al., 2015; van Dijck et al., 2015). These findings have been extended in other studies to include overlap between non-manipulable object size and numbers (Gabay et al., 2013), weight and numbers (Holmes and Lourenco, 2013), and sound volume and numbers (Heinemann et al., 2013).

Note that both grip and number specify magnitude in a general way (overlap) while words of valence and numbers (such as hero and 9) do not directly represent spatial displacement (and thus require an attentional interface). One theory that details how numerical magnitude can be related to an associated property in another domain (e.g., grasp aperture) is A Theory of Magnitude (ATOM; Walsh, 2003, 2015). ATOM argues that number, duration, quantity, as well as other similar concepts share a generalized magnitude system. In other words, these representations have a partially overlapping architecture that potentiates interactions between them. ATOM makes a general and theoretically broad case for representational overlap with regard to magnitude and provides both behavioral and neuroanatomical evidence for the existence of representations with an overlapping magnitude component (but see Van Opstal and Verguts, 2013, for a critique of ATOM). As such, Figure 1B portrays a general case of ATOM as described by Walsh (2003, 2015).

Similarly, to the role of attention in the interface-based cross-representational interactions, magnitude acts as our showcase instance of overlap-based interactions. However, we believe this is not the only such mechanism. Two other mediators we propose as candidates for the cross-representational overlap are sequencing and affect. Although, there is limited research on how the brain’s sequencing system is involved during conceptual processing, recent neuroscientific research has attributed a special role to the cerebellum among other structures within a network supporting processes of chunking, patterning, and sequencing of different stimuli including sounds, words, and numbers (Dehaene et al., 2015). For example, the cerebellum has been implicated in mathematical cognition as well as in grammatical processes and music perception (Doya, 1999; Riva and Giorgi, 2000; Janata and Grafton, 2003; Wartenburger et al., 2003; Murdoch, 2010; Pliatsikas et al., 2014; Dehaene et al., 2015). We suggest that the brain network responsible for patterning, sequencing, and chunking can mediate cross-representational interaction effects for the concepts that rely heavily on hierarchical organization of linear sequences such as grammatical, arithmetic, and musical phrases (Scheepers et al., 2011; Van de Cavey and Hartsuiker, 2016; Van de Cavey et al., 2016).

Another possible overlap mediator is affect. Existing research (e.g., Berridge and Kringelbach, 2013) describes the affective system of the brain as a distinct network of cortical and subcortical (e.g., amygdala) structures involved during processing of emotional stimuli. This network’s components were previously shown to support processing of emotional words (Naccache et al., 2005) and emotional face judgements (Morris et al., 1998; Sheline et al., 2001; Pegna et al., 2005). One prediction would be that interactions between different valence projecting stimuli (e.g., words and faces) will lead to the registration of interaction effects similar to those described above for magnitude-based representations.

A Case for Mixed Cases

The two-route mechanism described above suggests that while the overlapping feature is an integral part of a stored representation, the interface mediator emerges as a property of a situated context that supports interaction via simultaneously available reference to general cognitive mechanisms (e.g., attention) (cf. Jackendoff, 2002). Of course, one can assume that a reference or a command to interface with attentional networks when going online can be a permanent feature of a stored representation. In this case, this feature needs to be shared by the interacting representations. Finally, we postulate that interface and overlap mechanisms are distinct because one can test their activation differentially. Consider, for example, concepts denoting emotional valence may have two simultaneously available mechanisms allowing them to interact with other concepts: (1) an online interface mechanism based on attentional displacement and (2) an off-line overlap mechanism based on affect. Theoretically, these mechanisms can be activated simultaneously as well as independently. For example, interactions between numbers and valence words can be supported by an attentional interface while interactions between emotional faces and valence words can be supported by an affective overlap (cf. Holmes and Lourenco, 2009). In the same logic, time can also have different mapping mechanisms simultaneously available as the basis for interaction with other concepts: an attentional interface for the representation of the past vs. the future and magnitude-related overlap for the conceptualization of duration (e.g., Ma et al., 2012). Similarly, even the same interface type (e.g., spatial attention) can have simultaneously available mappings along different spatial dimensions. A recent study by Pitt and Casasanto (2016) provides an intriguing demonstration that, while the polarity of emotional valence (good vs. bad) tends to map vertically, its magnitude has a stronger representation in horizontal space. Papies (2013) used a similar approach in order to distinguish semantic and grounded/embodied features of food representations (cf. Freddi et al., 2016).

Further research is necessary in order to investigate the nature of these and similar representational pairs with flexible interaction systems. One particular question is whether the overlap and interface interaction systems are activated independently or whether the cognitive system habitually uses both interfaces at the same time, thus making the established interaction structure stronger. The examples from the spatial-numerical domain given last suggest that attentional interfaces are more rapidly established and modulated, and thus have a substantially faster time course of engagement when compared to the featural overlap mechanism: scanning number words from right to left (in Hebrew) or from left to right (in Russian) modulated the SNARC effect within seconds, while reading text with small and large numbers positioned in a SNARC-congruent vs. SNARC-incongruent way only gradually led to a modulation of the SNARC effect over several minutes. Other predictions stemming from our proposal concern the brain regions involved in setting up attentional vs. featural interfaces. Specifically, cross-representational interactions established via an attentional interface should be accompanied by cortical activations within well-known attentional networks (Fan et al., 2005) while interactions aided by featural interfaces should be less dependent on such focal activations and instead activate distributed brain areas that represent distinct knowledge domains as well as cerebellar structures.

Finally, with regard to the acquisition of semantic interfaces, one implication of our proposal is that, by means of a repeatedly shared attentional mechanism, any two seemingly distinct knowledge representations may eventually interact once they each have become associated with systematically overlapping sensory or motor features. Thus, a Hebbian learning mechanism will eventually transform the attentional interface into a structural overlap that supports efficient cognition (Pulvermüller, 2013).

Conclusion

In this paper, we made a theoretical proposal for two distinct interaction systems for grounded representations. We suggest that representing and activating knowledge in distinct conceptual domains is based on sensorimotor simulation, and further suggest that representations from different domains can interact either via a third party online interface or by permanently sharing a feature allowing for a representational overlap. We argue that our proposal is supported by evidence from research on number processing, words of emotional valence, and conceptual and linguistic concepts of manipulable objects. We hope this short sketch of proposed mechanisms and their basic features will encourage future integrative research on cross-representational interaction mechanisms.

Ethics Statement

The research referred to in this paper has been approved by the Ethics Committee of Psychology Department, Northumbria University. Participants provided informed written consent.

Author Contributions

AM, AC, and MF have contributed equally to this submission.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgment

The work has been supported by the Russian Academic Excellence Project ‘5-100’.

Footnotes

  1. ^Here, we use the term “apparently abstract” whenever we refer to concepts that are traditionally rendered disembodied, experience-independent, and/or symbolic (e.g., Dove, 2009; Chatterjee, 2010; Zwaan, 2014).

References

Abrahamse, E., van Dijck, J.-P., and Fias, W. (2016). How does working memory enable number-induced spatial biases? Front. Psychol. 7:977. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00977

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Andres, M., Davare, M., Pesenti, M., Olivier, E., and Seron, X. (2004). Number magnitude and grip aperture interaction. Neuroreport 15, 2773–2777.

Google Scholar

Andres, M., Ostry, D. J., Nicol, F., and Paus, T. (2008). Time course of number magnitude interference during grasping. Cortex 44, 414–419. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2007.08.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baddeley, A. (1986). Working memory. Oxford Psychology Series, No. 11. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptions of perceptual symbols. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 637–660. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X99532147

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 617–645. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093639

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (2009). Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Biol. Sci. 364, 1281–1289. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2008.0319

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berridge, K. C., and Kringelbach, M. L. (2013). Neuroscience of affect: brain mechanisms of pleasure and displeasure. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 23, 294–303. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2013.01.017

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bonato, M., Zorzi, M., and Umiltà, C. (2012). When time is space: evidence for a mental time line. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 36, 2257–2273. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2012.08.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bottini, R., Crepaldi, D., Casasanto, D., Crollen, V., and Collignon, O. (2015). Space and time in the sighted and blind. Cognition 141, 67–72. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2015.04.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brunel, L., Labeye, E., Lesourd, M., and Versace, R. (2009). The sensory nature of episodic memory: sensory priming effects due to memory trace activation. J. Exp. Psychol. 35, 1081. doi: 10.1037/a0015537

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cappelletti, M., Freeman, E. D., and Cipolotti, L. (2009). Dissociations and interactions between time, numerosity and space processing. Neuropsychologia 47, 2732–2748. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.05.024

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chatterjee, A. (2010). Disembodying cognition. Lang. Cogn. 2, 79–116. doi: 10.1515/langcog.2010.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chiou, R. Y. C., Chang, E. C., Tzeng, O. J. L., and Wu, D. H. (2009). The common magnitude code underlying numerical and size processing for action but not for perception. Exp. Brain Res. 194, 553–562. doi: 10.1007/s00221-009-1730-8

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cowan, N. (2005). Working Memory Capacity. Hove: Psychology Press.

Google Scholar

Dehaene, S., Bossini, S., and Giraux, P. (1993). The mental representation of parity and number magnitude. J. Exp. Psychol. 122, 371. doi: 10.1037/0096-3445.122.3.371

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dehaene, S., Meyniel, F., Wacongne, C., Wang, L., and Pallier, C. (2015). The neural representation of sequences: from transition probabilities to algebraic patterns and linguistic trees. Neuron 88, 2–19. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2015.09.019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dove, G. (2009). Beyond perceptual symbols: a call for representational pluralism. Cognition 110, 412–431. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2008.11.016

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Doya, K. (1999). What are the computations of the cerebellum, the basal ganglia and the cerebral cortex? Neural Netw. 12, 961–974. doi: 10.1016/S0893-6080(99)00046-5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fan, J., McCandliss, B. D., Fossella, J., Flombaum, J. I., and Posner, M. I. (2005). The activation of attentional networks. Neuroimage 26, 471–479. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2005.02.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fischer, M. (2003). Spatial representations in number processing–evidence from a pointing task. Vis. Cogn. 10, 493–508. doi: 10.1080/13506280244000186

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fischer, M. H., and Shaki, S. (2014). Spatial associations in numerical cognition–From single digits to arithmetic. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 67, 1461–1483. doi: 10.1080/17470218.2014.927515

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fischer, M. H., Warlop, N., Hill, R. L., and Fias, W. (2004). Oculomotor bias induced by number perception. Exp. Psychol. 51, 91–97. doi: 10.1027/1618-3169.51.2.91

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fodor, J. A. (1983). The Modularity of Mind: An Essay On Faculty Psychology. Cambridge MA: MIT press.

Google Scholar

Foroni, F., and Semin, G. R. (2009). Language that puts you in touch with your bodily feelings the multimodal responsiveness of affective expressions. Psychol. Sci. 20, 974–980. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2009.02400.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Freddi, S., Brouillet, T., Cretenet, J., Heurley, L. P., and Dru, V. (2016). A continuous mapping between space and valence with left-and right-handers. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23, 865–870. doi: 10.3758/s13423-015-0950-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gabay, S., Leibovich, T., Henik, A., and Gronau, N. (2013). Size before numbers: conceptual size primes numerical value. Cognition 129, 18–23. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.06.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gianelli, C., Ranzini, M., Marzocchi, M., Micheli, L. R., and Borghi, A. M. (2012). Influence of numerical magnitudes on the free choice of an object position. Cogn. Process. 13, 185–188. doi: 10.1007/s10339-012-0483-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hayashi, M. J., Valli, A., and Carlson, S. (2013). Numerical quantity affects time estimation in the suprasecond range. Neurosci. Lett. 543, 7–11. doi: 10.1016/j.neulet.2013.02.054

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Heinemann, A., Pfister, R., and Janczyk, M. (2013). Manipulating number generation: loud+ long = large? Consci. Cogn. 22, 1332–1339. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2013.08.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Holmes, K. J., and Lourenco, S. F. (2009). “Spatial organization of magnitude in the representation of number and emotion,” in Proceedings of the 31th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Austin, TX, 2402–2407.

Google Scholar

Holmes, K. J., and Lourenco, S. F. (2011). Common spatial organization of number and emotional expression: a mental magnitude line. Brain Cogn. 77, 315–323. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2011.07.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Holmes, K. J., and Lourenco, S. F. (2013). When numbers get heavy: is the mental number line exclusively numerical? PLoS One 8:e58381. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0058381

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Janata, P., and Grafton, S. T. (2003). Swinging in the brain: shared neural substrates for behaviors related to sequencing and music. Nat. Neurosci. 6, 682–687. doi: 10.1038/nn1081

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lachmair, M., Dudschig, C., de la Vega, I., and Kaup, B. (2014a). Relating numeric cognition and language processing: do numbers and words share a common representational platform? Acta Psychol. 148, 107–114. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2013.12.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lachmair, M., Dudschig, C., Ruiz Fernández, S., and Kaup, B. (2014b). Numbers affect the processing of verbs denoting movements in vertical space. Cogn. Process. 15, S115–S117.

Google Scholar

Lewandowsky, S. (2016). #symbodiment: God may Really be up there but Perhaps your Lips don’t Listen? (Special Virtual Issue of Psychonomic Bulletin & Review). Avaialable at: http://www.psychonomic.org/featured-content-detail/symbodiment-god-may-really-be-up-there-perhaps-you

Lindemann, O., Abolafia, J. M., Girardi, G., and Bekkering, H. (2007). Getting a grip on numbers: numerical magnitude priming in object grasping. J. Exp. Psychol. 33, 1400.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Ma, Q., Yang, Z., and Zhang, Z. (2012). The modulation of implicit magnitude on time estimates. PLoS ONE 7:e46471. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0046471

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mahon, B. Z. (2015). What is embodied about cognition? Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 30, 420–429. doi: 10.1080/23273798.2014.987791

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2008). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. J. Physiol. Paris 102, 59–70. doi: 10.1016/j.jphysparis.2008.03.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meier, B. P., and Robinson, M. D. (2004). Why the sunny side is up associations between affect and vertical position. Psychol. Sci. 15, 243–247. doi: 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.00659.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B., and Vigliocco, G. (2012). Coming of age: a review of embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex 48, 788–804. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2010.11.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moretto, G., and Di Pellegrino, G. (2008). Grasping numbers. Exp. Brain Res. 188, 505–515. doi: 10.1007/s00221-008-1386-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Morris, J. S., Öhman, A., and Dolan, R. J. (1998). Conscious and unconscious emotional learning in the human amygdala. Nature 393, 467–470. doi: 10.1038/30976

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Murdoch, B. E. (2010). The cerebellum and language: historical perspective and review. Cortex 46, 858–868. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2009.07.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Myachykov, A., Ellis, R., Cangelosi, A., and Fischer, M. H. (2016). Ocular drift along the mental number line. Psychol. Res. 80, 379–388. doi: 10.1007/s00426-015-0731-4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Myachykov, A., Scheepers, C., Fischer, M. H., and Kessler, K. (2014). TEST: a tropic, embodied, situated theory of cognition. Top. Cogn. Sci. 6, 442–460. doi: 10.1111/tops.12024

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Naccache, L., Gaillard, R., Adam, C., Hasboun, D., Clémenceau, S., Baulac, M., et al. (2005). A direct intracranial record of emotions evoked by subliminal words. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102, 7713–7717. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0500542102

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Namdar, G., Tzelgov, J., Algom, D., and Ganel, T. (2014). Grasping numbers: evidence for automatic influence of numerical magnitude on grip aperture. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 21, 830–835. doi: 10.3758/s13423-013-0550-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Núñez, R., and Cooperrider, K. (2013). The tangle of space and time in human cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17, 220–229. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2013.03.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Papies, E. K. (2013). Tempting food words activate eating simulations. Front. Psychol. 4:838. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00838

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pegna, A. J., Khateb, A., Lazeyras, F., and Seghier, M. L. (2005). Discriminating emotional faces without primary visual cortices involves the right amygdala. Nat. Neurosci. 8, 24–25. doi: 10.1038/nn1364

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pitt, B., and Casasanto, D. (2016). “Spatializing emotion: a mapping of valence or magnitude?,” in Proceedings of the 38th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, eds D. Grodner, D. Mirman, A. Papafragou, and J. Trueswell (Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society), 1056–1061.

Google Scholar

Pliatsikas, C., Johnstone, T., and Marinis, T. (2014). Grey matter volume in the cerebellum is related to the processing of grammatical rules in a second language: a structural voxel-based morphometry study. Cerebellum 13, 55–63. doi: 10.1007/s12311-013-0515-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Posner, M. I. (1980). Orienting of attention. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 32, 3–25. doi: 10.1080/00335558008248231

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Posner, M. I., and Fan, J. (2008). Attention as an organ system. Top. Integr. Neurosci. 26, 31–61. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511541681.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pulvermüller, F. (1999). Words in the brain’s language. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 253–279. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X9900182X

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pulvermüller, F. (2013). How neurons make meaning: brain mechanisms for embodied and abstract-symbolic semantics. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17, 458–470. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2013.06.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ranzini, M., Lisi, M., Blini, E., Pitteri, M., Treccani, B., Priftis, K., et al. (2015). Larger, smaller, odd or even? Task-specific effects of optokinetic stimulation on the mental number space. J. Cogn. Psychol. 27, 459–470. doi: 10.1080/20445911.2014.941847

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ranzini, M., Lugli, L., Anelli, F., Carbone, R., Nicoletti, R., and Borghi, A. M. (2011). Graspable objects shape number processing. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 5:147. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2011.00147

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rey, A. E., Riou, B., Muller, D., Dabic, S., and Versace, R. (2015). “The mask who wasn’t there”: visual masking effect with the perceptual absence of the mask. J. Exp. Psychol. 41, 567. doi: 10.1037/xlm0000051

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Richardson, D. C., Spivey, M. J., Barsalou, L. W., and McRae, K. (2003). Spatial representations activated during real-time comprehension of verbs. Cogn. Sci. 27, 767–780. doi: 10.1207/s15516709cog2705_4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Riou, B., Rey, A. E., Vallet, G. T., Cuny, C., and Versace, R. (2015). Perceptual processing affects the reactivation of a sensory dimension during a categorization task. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 68, 1223–1230. doi: 10.1080/17470218.2014.978876

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Riva, D., and Giorgi, C. (2000). The cerebellum contributes to higher functions during development. Brain 123, 1051–1061. doi: 10.1093/brain/123.5.1051

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rizzolatti, G., Riggio, L., and Sheliga, B. M. (1994). “Space and selective attention,” in Attention and Performance XV, eds C. Umilta and M. Moscovitch (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 231–265.

Google Scholar

Santiago, J., and Lakens, D. (2015). Can conceptual congruency effects between number, time, and space be accounted for by polarity correspondence? Acta Psychol. 156, 179–191. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2014.09.016

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scheepers, C., Sturt, P., Martin, C. J., Myachykov, A., and Teevan, K. (2011). Structural priming across cognitive domains: from simple algebra to relative clause attachment. Psychol. Sci. 22, 1319–1326. doi: 10.1177/0956797611416997

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sheline, Y. I., Barch, D. M., Donnelly, J. M., Ollinger, J. M., Snyder, A. Z., and Mintun, M. A. (2001). Increased amygdala response to masked emotional faces in depressed subjects resolves with antidepressant treatment: an fMRI study. Biol. Psychiatry 50, 651–658. doi: 10.1016/S0006-3223(01)01263-X

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van de Cavey, J., and Hartsuiker, R. J. (2016). Is there a domain-general cognitive structuring system? Evidence from structural priming across music, math, action descriptions, and language. Cognition 146, 172–184. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2015.09.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van de Cavey, J., Severens, E., and Hartsuiker, R. J. (2016). Shared structuring resources across domains: double task effects from linguistic processing on the structural integration of pitch sequences. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. doi: 10.1080/17470218.2016.1195852 [Epub ahead of print],

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van Dijck, J. P., Fias, W., and Andres, M. (2015). Selective interference of grasp and space representations with number magnitude and serial order processing. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 22, 1370–1376. doi: 10.3758/s13423-014-0788-x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van Opstal, F., and Verguts, T. (2013). Is there a generalized magnitude system in the brain? behavioral, neuroimaging, and computational evidence. Front. Psychol. 4:435. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00435

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vigliocco, G., Vinson, D. P., Lewis, W., and Garrett, M. F. (2004). Representing the meanings of object and action words: the featural and unitary semantic space hypothesis. Cognit. Psychol. 48, 422–488. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2003.09.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walsh, V. (2003). A theory of magnitude: common cortical metrics of time, space and quantity. Trends Cogn. Sciences 7, 483–488. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2003.09.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walsh, V. (2015). “A theory of magnitude: the parts that sum to number,” in The Oxford Handbook of Numerical Cognition, eds R. Cohen Kadosh and A. Dowker (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 552–565.

Google Scholar

Wartenburger, I., Heekeren, H. R., Abutalebi, J., Cappa, S. F., Villringer, A., and Perani, D. (2003). Early setting of grammatical processing in the bilingual brain. Neuron 37, 159–170. doi: 10.1016/S0896-6273(02)01150-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9, 625–636. doi: 10.3758/BF03196322

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Winter, B., Marghetis, T., and Matlock, T. (2015). Of magnitudes and metaphors: explaining cognitive interactions between space, time, and number. Cortex 64, 209–224. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2014.10.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwaan, R. A. (2014). Embodiment and language comprehension: reframing the discussion. Trends Cogn. Sci. 18, 229–234. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.02.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: representation, cross-representational interaction, simulation, embodiment, grounded cognition

Citation: Myachykov A, Chapman AJ and Fischer MH (2017) Cross-Representational Interactions: Interface and Overlap Mechanisms. Front. Psychol. 7:2028. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.02028

Received: 07 September 2016; Accepted: 13 December 2016;
Published: 04 January 2017.

Edited by:

Lionel Brunel, Paul Valéry University, Montpellier III, France

Reviewed by:

Rémy Versace, Lumière University Lyon 2, France
Loïc P. Heurley, Paris West University Nanterre La Défense, France

Copyright © 2017 Myachykov, Chapman and Fischer. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Andriy Myachykov, andriy.myachykov@northumbria.ac.uk

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.