Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 24 February 2017
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

Empathy-Related Responses to Depicted People in Art Works

  • 1Applied Neurosciences and Brain Imaging, National Institute of Mental Health, Klecany, Czechia
  • 2Department of Art History, Masaryk University Brno, Brno, Czechia

Existing theories of empathic response to visual art works postulate the primacy of automatic embodied reaction to images based on mirror neuron mechanisms. Arguing for a more inclusive concept of empathy-related response and integrating four distinct bodies of literature, we discuss contextual, and personal factors which modulate empathic response to depicted people. We then present an integrative model of empathy-related responses to depicted people in art works. The model assumes that a response to empathy-eliciting figural artworks engages the dynamic interaction of two mutually interlinked sets of processes: socio-affective/cognitive processing, related to the person perception, and esthetic processing, primarily concerned with esthetic appreciation and judgment and attention to non-social aspects of the image. The model predicts that the specific pattern of interaction between empathy-related and esthetic processing is co-determined by several sets of factors: (i) the viewer's individual characteristics, (ii) the context variables (which include various modes of priming by narratives and other images), (iii) multidimensional features of the image, and (iv) aspects of a viewer's response. Finally we propose that the model is implemented by the interaction of functionally connected brain networks involved in socio-cognitive and esthetic processing.

Introduction

Empathy-related phenomena occupy a central place in contemporary neuropsychology and social and affective neuroscience. This research agenda, spurred both by the rapid spread of neuroimaging, and new conceptual models, has been accompanied in the past two decades by the rediscovery of empathy in the humanities, particularly in art history and theory and in film studies. In itself, this rediscovery can be set within the larger context of what might loosely be termed the “bodily” and the “emotional” turn in the humanities and social sciences (Papoulias and Callard, 2010; Lanzoni, 2012). It is increasingly evident that empathy-related issues offer the possibility for productive interfacing between the sciences of the mind and brain and the humanities. Within the humanities, the role of embodied meaning-making in pictorial and esthetic experience has been examined not only in more philosophical and theoretical writings (e.g., Curtis and Koch, 2009; Coplan and Goldie, 2011) but also in art-historical and critical texts devoted to specific works of art written by some of the leading art historians of our times. Scholars such as Leo Steinberg and Michael Fried have written rich and nuanced accounts of bodily projection and empathic engagements with works of art (Steinberg, 1988, 2001; Fried, 2002). Many works of visual art engage and facilitate complex emotional and empathic reactions, thereby potentially serving as a testing ground for such complex reactions in real-life situations.

The best art-historical accounts of embodiment and emotional engagement with works of art, such as Steinberg's and Fried's, operate on the level of behavioral explanation and are firmly rooted in the phenomenology of their authors' viewing experience, without taking into consideration the current conceptualizations of emotional and empathic reactions. On the other hand, cognitive-psychological and neuroscientific accounts of empathic response to works of art do not, as a rule, incorporate the subjective accounts of actual viewing experiences and/or relevant art-historical facts (Kandel, 2012). However, it is increasingly recognized (see e.g., Bullot and Reber, 2013; psycho-historical framework for empirical esthetics; also Bergeron and Lopes, 2014; Gopnik, 2014) that disregarding the historical and subjective dimensions of artworks, which is typical in the neuroscience of art, actually hinders progress in the field. The specific problem of empathic response to visual artworks spans multiple research fields and requires cross-fertilization among at least four distinct and extensive literatures: (i) the psychology and neuroscience of empathy-related phenomena and the affective processing of visual stimuli; (ii) empirical esthetics/neuroesthetics; (iii) problems of immersion and simulation in fictive worlds; and (iv) relevant art-historical and critical scholarship. In this paper we integrate these literatures in an effort to demonstrate that theoretical models of emotional and empathic response to works of art (which could be used to formulate hypotheses and guide future empirical research) must not be insulated from at least some account of actual experiential engagement with works of art and from art-historical facts. Consequently, after briefly discussing the limits of current models of empathic response to visual art works, we discuss several key modulating factors, focusing primarily on interlinked contextual frames (Section Contextual Framing: Pictorial, Spatial-Experiential, and Cultural Contexts) and the role of the representational medium in staging a “reality effect” (or witness perspective) in empathic response (Section The Role of the Representational Medium and the Reality-Effect in Empathic Response). With this background, we then proceed to outline an integrative model of empathy-related response to figural art works (Section An Integrated Model of Empathy-Related Responses to Figural Artworks).

The Limitations of Current Models of Empathic Response to Visual Art Works

Arguably the best-known attempt to link current neuroscientific research on empathy to visual art is that of Freedberg and Gallese (2007). Their theory stems from Gallese's embodied simulation hypothesis, which posits that the mirror-neuron system allows human subjects to directly understand the meaning not only of others' actions but also of their emotions by internally replicating them without any explicit reflective cognition (Gallese, 2003; Gallese et al., 2004). Consequently, Freedberg and Gallese argue against the primacy of cognition in our responses to art. They claim that the “crucial element of esthetic response” involves the activation of universal embodied mechanisms encompassing the simulation of actions, emotions and corporeal sensation, and they conclude: “Automatic empathetic responses constitute a basic level of response to images and to works of art. Underlying such responses is the process of embodied simulation that enables the direct experiential understanding of the intentional and emotional contents of images. The basic level of reaction to images becomes essential to any understanding of their effectiveness as art” (Freedberg and Gallese, 2007, p. 202).

Briefly admitting the importance of historical and contextual factors, they insist that they “do not contradict the importance of “basic mechanisms” of response” (ibid; see also Freedberg, 2007; Gallese, 2010). Elsewhere Freedberg claims that the impact of an image such as Rogier van der Weyden's Descent from the Cross on both the fifteenth-century and the modern-day viewer would depend on “…a set of cortical responses that have little to do with context…but everything to do with the connection between sight of the bodies and movements of others and the viewers' sense of their own bodies and movements” (Freedberg, 2011, p. 345–346, emphasis added). Freedberg and Gallese's account apparently simplifies what is a much more complicated process. It has already been criticized on several grounds (Casati and Pignocchi, 2007; Kesner, 2010; Gallagher, 2011; Krois, 2011; Davies, 2014; Schott, 2015; for the most detailed criticism, see Minissale, 2013, p. 84–108), so we shall reiterate only the main point here, which is that the role of embodied simulation (and the mirror-neuron system—hereafter MNS) as the underlying neural mechanism in a viewer's complex understanding of works of art or indeed images is questionable. The authors write: “viewers report bodily empathy,” “viewers often experience,” “most spectators of works of art are familiar with feelings of empathetic engagements with what they see in the work itself” (our emphasis). They argue that embodied simulation is crucial for a direct experiential understanding of images, which is essential to their effectiveness as art. But while we take the first-person accounts of art experience as indispensable source of information, there is little empirical evidence to support such generalizations about viewers' experiences. Moreover, there is scant evidence for the role of MNS in empathic response to art, and most importantly, the empathic response, on our account, cannot be limited to motor resonance with depicted bodies. This is aptly summarized by Minissale: “It could be said that not only does Freedberg overemphasize the importance of empathy in art, but that he also promotes a particularly simplistic form of empathy” (Minissale, 2013, p. 104). While the merits of the simulation theory of empathy and the role of MNS in empathy-related responses to socially salient signals continue to be subjects of intense debate (e.g., Decety, 2010b; Baird et al., 2011; Fan et al., 2011; Gallese and Sinigaglia, 2011; Hickok, 2013; Spaulding, 2013; Caramazza et al., 2014; Mikulan et al., 2014; Ando et al., 2015; Gallese and Caruana, 2016), many authors agree that the MNS does not play a substantive role in understanding emotions and empathic response. As Lamm and Majdandžic (2015, p. 20) recently summarized, “…empathy neither requires, nor can be exhaustively explained by “mirror neurons”. However, it is not our intention here either to dismiss the simulation model of empathy or to deny any role for MNS in the empathic and possibly esthetic experience of art works. Rather, we emphasize that affective resonance heavily depends on a viewer's cognitively elaborated understanding of the depicted person's (and/or the artist's) state of mind, as well as their circumstances, that is, on an extensive imaginative projection, and thus the role of embodied simulation (and MNS as its neural substrate) in reflective empathic experience appears to be rather limited. Consequently, we aim to replace current accounts of (narrowly defined) empathic response to visual arts, which exclusively focus on automatic embodied simulation and MNS activation (Freedberg and Gallese, 2007; Kandel, 2012), with a more inclusive model capable of incorporating empathy-related responses to depicted people within the broader pictorial experience. After all, understanding the power of images to elicit affective and empathic responses in their viewers—a subject of long-standing interest—continues to pose a research challenge with profound social implications.

Varieties of Empathy and the Modulatory Factors of Empathy—A Conceptual Framework

Given the semantic density of the term “empathy” and the terminological inconsistencies surrounding its usage (among recent reviews, see, e.g., Batson, 2009; Cuff et al., 2014), it is not surprising that in discussions of empathy in art, the concept is used to refer to different things—from embodied projection into depicted bodies to feelings of compassion elicited by images. While there is no agreed upon definition of empathy, there is a broad consensus that an evolutionary younger cognitive system is layered on top of affective processes, with the more ancient and more direct visceral-motor mechanism providing scaffolding for more advanced cognitive elaboration and description (Gallese et al., 2004; Keysers and Gazzola, 2009; Shamay-Tsoory et al., 2009; Decety, 2010a, 2011; Fan et al., 2011; Bernhardt and Singer, 2012). Alternatively, empathy-related responses can be conceptualized as involving three domains: motor, affective, and cognitive empathy (Decety and Meyer, 2008). Much attention has been focused lately on the mutual integration and cooperation of the neural structures subserving these domains (Shamay-Tsoory et al., 2009; Cox et al., 2012; Sebastian et al., 2012; Spunt and Lieberman, 2012; Zaki and Ochsner, 2012; Gonzalez-Liencres et al., 2013; Kanske et al., 2015; Mitchell and Phillips, 2015; Schlaffke et al., 2015).

We acknowledge that the response to a work of figural art can in some instances take the form of (largely reflexive) motor resonance with the depicted body or with pictorial elements of the painting (along the lines envisaged in the notion of Einfühlung, as originally formulated by Vischer (1873) and Lipps (1903) and as discussed by Freedberg and Gallese (2007), without any further cognitive elaboration. However, here we use the term empathy in a more inclusive sense, as referring to the ability to feel and understand what the depicted subject is seen as experiencing. Following a number of influential accounts (e.g., Batson, 1991; Davis, 1996; Decety and Jackson, 2004; Keen, 2006; De Vignemont and Jacob, 2012; Gallagher, 2012; Walter, 2012; Zaki and Ochsner, 2012; Clarke et al., 2015), we take empathy to be more than automatic mirroring and contagion. Instead, it incorporates (i) affective response to a depicted person (sometimes labeled affective empathy), (ii) cognitive understanding, which provides some insight into that person's mental state and situation (sometimes labeled cognitive empathy or affective mentalizing), and (iii) a clear sense of self–other distinction, which precludes the confusing the self with the target. On such an account, empathy involves experiencing in some measure the depicted person's emotional state, that is, it involves: recognition, some degree of understanding and, in most cases, at least some affective resonance or sharing of the inferred mental state. Given the fact that emotional expressions in art works are often intentionally ambiguous and understanding their meaning requires active inference by the viewer, we submit that the affectivity condition (for empathy) is met even when a viewer's response does not match the most plausible interpretation of the depicted state.1

The title of the article, “empathy-related responses” is chosen deliberately to embrace both empathy and the closely related phenomenon of compassion or empathic concern, whose distinct behavioral and neuronal profiles have been increasingly acknowledged by some theorists (Bernhardt and Singer, 2012; Klimecki et al., 2013; Singer and Klimecki, 2014). A viewer's reaction to the depicted suffering and misfortune of others can incorporate either self-oriented empathic distress (feeling with the depicted figures), or other-oriented compassion (feeling for them), or in most cases, some combination of both components. Importantly for works of visual art, in both aspects the empathic response may in some cases (most frequently in self-portraits) extend from real or imaginary depicted person(s) to the artist, whose presence is either enacted in the image or implied by contextual information.

Empathic response is commonly understood to be strongly modulated both by context and by individual personal characteristics. The main modulating factors, as a number of neuroimaging studies has revealed, include: the intensity of displayed emotion, the appraisal of a situation, the characteristics of the person suffering, attention, the personality traits of the empathizer, previous experience of situations that inflict pain, the degree of attachment to the target, the degree of potential vulnerability or helplessness of an object (Watt, 2005; Gu and Han, 2007; Hein and Singer, 2008; Bernhardt and Singer, 2012; Rameson et al., 2012; Gonzalez-Liencres et al., 2013). The empathic response to visual art works is similarly subject to manifold top-down appraisals and modulations. In what follows we focus on three key factors: (i) contextual framing, which can include various modes of priming by narratives and other images and which co-determines patterns of visual exploration of the image; (ii) a unique combination of the personal dispositions of the beholder; and (iii) the characteristics of the image, including the nature and format of the representational medium.

Contextual Framing: Pictorial, Spatial-Experiential, and Cultural Contexts

The crucial role of context in social cognition generally and empathic response specifically has received increasing attention lately (e.g., Bernhardt and Singer, 2012; Ibañez and Manes, 2012; Melloni et al., 2014). Likewise, the central role of context in art experience is well-established and recent neurocognitive models of art experience highlight the importance of various contextual factors (e.g., Jacobsen, 2006; Bullot and Reber, 2013; Redies, 2015). A number of studies in experimental esthetics have examined various forms of text-based contextual priming (e.g., Millis, 2001; Leder et al., 2006; Smith et al., 2006; Kirk et al., 2009; Noguchi and Murota, 2013; Swami, 2013; Gerger et al., 2014; Silveira et al., 2015), as well as effects of spatial and institutional settings (Brieber et al., 2014, 2015; Krukar, 2014) on art appreciation and experience. For the present purpose, we suggest that three contextual frames must be distinguished: first, the pictorial context of the image, i.e., the relationship of the emotionally salient aspects (affective affordances) to the pictorial field or structure as a whole; second, the spatial and experiential context of the presentation of the image; and third, the cultural-social context of the actual experiential situation, in which the viewer's personal dispositions interact with cultural factors and form expectations. To address the complexities of the contextual priming of empathic response to depicted pain and physical suffering, we now turn to considering a specific example of an art work—The Blinding of Samson by Rembrandt from 1,636 (Figure 1). The subject of the painting is the biblical story of the blinding of Samson by the Philistines, which focuses on the cataclysmic effect of agony and on the moment when the actual mutilation takes place. Several authors have highlighted the emotional appeal and effectiveness of the painting. As memorably phrased by art historian Kenneth Clark: “The Blinding of Samson is an extremely disturbing picture. Only a man of genius could have done anything so consistently horrifying. Apart from the revolting realism of the actual blinding, every detail, every hand and foot, is ugly in itself” (Clark, 1966, p.20). Other commentators describe the depicted scene as “gory” and as a “drama of extreme brutality” (Perlove and Silver, 2009, p.113), while the author of one of the many monographs on Rembrandt specifically notes that “…in front of this picture we realize the unique power of [Rembrandt's] empathy” (Štech V. V., 1966, p.73).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Rembrandt, Blinding of Samson, oil on canvas, 1636. Image source: Wikimedia Commons library.

Recall now the argument that “embodied simulation enables the direct experiential understanding of the intentional and emotional contents of images…” (Freedberg and Gallese, 2007, emphasis added). But what does this “direct experiential understanding” amount to in the case of the viewer looking at Blinding? We can begin by comparing such a “disturbing and horrifying” image that has the status of an artistic masterpiece to the kind of “emotionally negative” or “aversive” visual stimulus typically used in neuroimaging experiments on pain empathy, such as a naturalistic photograph of a needle being inserted into a hand (Lamm et al., 2007b; Ogino et al., 2007). The sensation of pain inflicted by a needle in a medical procedure will have been endured by most modern-day adults, who then will be able to directly access a vicarious feeling of such a sensation. On the other hand, the physical pain and mental suffering of having one's eyesight violently destroyed is (mercifully) outside the scope of personal experience of almost anyone who encounters The Blinding of Samson.

In the presumed empathic resonance with Samson (or the pain of a victim of similar such drastic images, such as Goya's Disasters of War or Nicolas Poussin's Martyrdom), the viewer can merely evoke a pain caused by whatever trauma to the body or given part of the body (s)he himself has encountered, which then has to be amplified through intentional empathic projection (De Greck et al., 2012) in order to model such unthinkable suffering. But there is obviously more to the depicted scene. Anyone who lost their eyesight through violence would be simultaneously thrust into a mental state of fear, desperation, distress, anger, and possibly many other feelings, that would compound the experience of pain (Price, 2000; Auvray et al., 2010), and this again is something that can only be approximated by the imagination. In fact, Samson's head represents a Gestalt, which encodes both the sensory and the affective components of pain (Kunz et al., 2012) and the effects of his fateful struggle. Thus, even in such persuasive depictions of pain, the experiential understanding, far from being automatic, and direct, appears to involve massive intentional projections by the viewer.

Pictorial Context

A major factor that constrains the nature of the empathic response to Samson's fate has to do with how the most emotionally salient aspects of the scene—what we shall label affective affordances (Fuchs and Koch, 2014; Kesner, 2014, see BOX)—are embedded within the overall pictorial space of the painting. In contrast to stimuli typically used in neuroimaging experiments on empathy for pain (e.g., an image showing a limb against the minimal background of a sheet of tissue, exhibiting uniform tonality and no texture, such as in an experiment by Ogino et al., 2007), in Rembrandt's painting, the relative placement of the main affective affordances within the entire pictorial composition assumes critical significance. The crucial details of Samson's head, with a dagger being driven into his right eye and blood and fluids oozing out, comprises roughly 1% of the entire pictorial field. Its imminent context is the struggling body of Samson, composed of a congruent body posture and facial expression. The perception of emotion conveyed by Samson's face is systematically influenced by the emotion expressed by his struggling body (on the contextual factors of the perception of emotional facial expression, see Meeren et al., 2005; Righart and De Gelder, 2008; Barrett et al., 2011; Wieser and Brosch, 2012; Kret et al., 2013).

Box 1. Affective affordance.

We define affective affordance as that component of the image that allows the affective and empathic response to unfold. It is comprised of both the low-level visual properties and the high-level intentional properties of an image. Affective affordances operate on several levels: (i) the level of virtual (depicted) objects and components thereof; (ii) the level of the elements that constitute the representational medium (the image-vehicle)—such as line, brushstrokes, or color; (iii) the level of the overall pictorial structure and composition. The affective salience of human bodies and faces depicted in works of art are always inherently enacted by how the artist works with the artistic medium. In some cases, the artist's intention complicates the activation of affective affordances, whereby the difference between a viewer's response to a real salient object (such as e.g., a face, or a gesture) and their response to a particular depiction of the object constitutes the artwork's esthetic effect (Kesner, 2016). Alongside body postures and gestures, the most important affective (and potentially social) affordances in a visual image are gaze and facial expression and their mutual interaction (see Graham and LaBar, 2012; Rigato and Farroni, 2013 for a review).

In attending to and scanning The Blinding, the detail of the head is a strong attractor. Nevertheless, it competes with other points of interest, both at the level of pictorial detail and the composition as a whole. The Blinding makes for perceptually an extremely complex scene. To make a quick and incomplete list of the affective and visual affordances vying with Samson's head for attention: on the level of objects, there are the faces and gazes of no fewer than five other figures, as well as their bodies, captured in dynamic movements and gestures, plus a number of other static objects. On the level of pictorial aspects, there is an interweaving of contrasts of light, from dramatic light to deep shadows, often set against each other, the color and texture of the clothes, or the metallic luster of the armor. Finally, there is the effect of the entire spatial setting of the composition, which both integrates the individual virtual objects depicted and addresses the viewer with its own dynamism. The composition enacts a dense interrelationship between the human figures depicted: on a phenomenological level, scanning away from Samson's agony to other figures and faces and/or other visual-semantic affordances provides a respite from direct engagement with the details of a painful situation (and thus could be described as down-regulating empathic response). At the same time, it is the viewer's unfolding awareness of these other figures' actions in relation to Samson's body that may reactivate empathic response to his suffering.

The active viewer inevitably negotiating his distance from the picture will thus be shifting between emotionally charged areas (affective affordances) and other points of visual interest or saliency. As recent eye-tracking studies have demonstrated, the eye initially tends to fixate on emotional objects rather than on other salient but emotionally neutral ones, and emotional saliency can override visual saliency that is defined by such features as intensity, color, and orientation (Humphrey et al., 2012; Massaro et al., 2012; Niu et al., 2012). The more closely the viewer attends to the picture plane, the greater the likelihood that his attention will be drawn to the surface of the painting, its texture and (other) visually salient features: e.g., the relative intensity of the tone, the distinctiveness or sharpness of the plane edges, optical differences, the way in which the depicted scenes and objects emerge from Rembrandt's handling of the medium. (The interaction between socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing will be discussed further in Section An Integrated Model of Empathy-Related Responses to Figural Artworks).

The Spatial-Experiential and Cultural Contexts

The experience of any art work is decisively shaped by the space in which it is presented. The viewer, by actively exercising her art viewing skills within the spatial/presentational context, determines and modulates the perception of affective affordances within the picture. The character and nature of empathic response will thus significantly depend on how a person goes about perceptually exploring the art work, involving both the movement of the body in relation to the painting's surface and scanning patterns exercised from a certain point in front of the picture. The viewer's individual pattern of sensory-motor response to an image directly impacts on processes of emotion-regulation and reappraisal, thereby co-determining the nature of the empathic response for the duration of the viewing period and shaping the process by which the picture is interpreted within the framework outlined in section An Integrated Model of Empathy-Related Responses to Figural Artworks. Moreover, the spatial-experiential context significantly shapes the response by providing various means of top-down influence and priming. Emerging evidence points to the role of context-specific information (such as titles of works, labels, and other texts) in making sense and in the appreciation of works of art (Leder et al., 2006; Smith et al., 2006; Kapoula et al., 2009; Silveira et al., 2015). The affective and empathic response to works of art is influenced by texts and narratives on two levels, with semantic information (i) directly guiding the patterns of attention and visual exploration of the work and (ii) providing an overall interpretative and evaluative framework within which the encounter with the work takes place. To provide a specific example, we shall briefly consider another art work—Giotto's Lamentation in the Scrovegni Chapel in Padua—as an example of a large category of medieval religious imagery, which can be said to contain a specific “script for action,” for an embodied reaction (Figure 2).

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Giotto di Bondone, Lamentation of Christ, Scrovegni chapel, Padua, wall painting, ca 1305. Image source: Wikimedia Commons library.

It has been well-established by art historians that scenes of the Passion of Christ, lamentations and other instances of social pain2 were efficacious in their original viewing conditions, often eliciting strong emotional responses in their viewers that were manifested in reactions such as weeping, kissing wounds, receiving stigmata, and other forms of embodied response (Belting, 1981; Ringbom, 1984; Freedberg, 1989; Bennett, 2001; Stevenson, 2010). One such account describes the response of Dominican writer Henry Suso's (1295–1366) mother when contemplating images in the Cathedral of Constance during Lent (as quoted in Hamburger, 1998, p. 237): “From pious contemplation of the worthy suffering of Christ, she felt in an acute manner the great pain that the compassionate mother of God experienced under the cross. And from her sensitivity to this affliction she fell ill in her body, so that she sank to the earth in a dead faint”. Devotional images were often encountered within a hierotopy (Lidov, 2006)—a multisensory space in which architecture, light, auditory and olfactory sensations all intermingled with the visual experience of images during liturgical ceremonies. Moreover, during communal worship the viewing of images was typically mediated and manipulated by the clergy—by the spoken exegesis of the priest—and even when contemplated privately the viewing of an image was often circumscribed by instructions in psalters, prayer books and paraliturgical compendia, which sometimes included specific instructions on where to direct the gaze (see Hamburger, 1998, p. 80–93). Priming by other sensory impressions and/or spoken or written words thereby functioned to target the gaze and to activate affective affordances within the image. Furthermore, especially in the setting of communal worship, the affective and empathic response was not just primed by words, but also by the socially sanctioned expectations of appropriate emotional display and behavior.

Such modulation and priming amounted to a comprehensive reappraisal and inferences based on historical facts can be thus assessed in the light of contemporary research on affective reappraisal (Wu et al., 2012; Lindquist and Gendron, 2013). Although experimentally verified evidence cannot be provided in the case of past audiences, it is plausible to speculate that semantic priming by words and liturgy may have served to identify and appraise affective affordances, co-determining the exogenous orienting of eye-scanning patterns, attentional allocation, or patterns of glancing vs. prolonged gazing at an image. Taking into account emerging evidence that empathic reaction, particularly the cognitive component, is modulated by the perceived closeness and relationship to the people depicted and affective resonance is limited to close others and extends to outgroup people only with active effort (e.g., Gutsell and Inzlicht, 2012; Eres and Molenberghs, 2013; Meyer et al., 2013), it is furthermore likely that affective resonance served to narrow the empathy gap between the observers and the persons depicted. In sum, priming by spoken or written words and implicit social norms offers an analogy to the regulation strategies used in contemporary experiments: instructions given to subjects to imagine themselves or loved ones in a depicted situation in order to heighten the sense of personal experience (Ochsner et al., 2004; Lamm et al., 2007a; Bebko et al., 2011). Importantly, many instances of contemporary audiences' encounters with pre-modern imagery of social pain are likewise cases of communal experience, in which listening to a live (a companion, a guide, a teacher) or recorded (audioguide) narrative decisively shapes the parameters of the visual encounter and hence how the experience unfolds. To sum up, both the original viewers and the modern-day audience are significantly pre-tuned by mutually dependent factors of their mind-set (participation in the framework of culturally sanctioned actions) and experiential and contextual situation. But crucially, both these factors are constrained by and only unfold through a third factor, namely, the nature of the representational medium that presents the target of the empathic response (as will be discussed in Section The Role of the Representational Medium and the Reality-Effect in Empathic Response).

Personal Factors Modulating the Empathic Response to Works of Art

An increasing body of evidence points to the crucial role of inter-subjective variation in the profile and the unfolding of both empathy-related responses and art experience. A number of neuroimaging experiments have demonstrated that the empathic response to the pain and emotions of others is modulated by personality traits and affective and cognitive styles (e.g., Avenanti et al., 2009; Calder et al., 2011; Lai et al., 2012). Trait and state anxiety, in particular, has been found to correlate with the magnitude of the response to emotional stimuli (Etkin et al., 2004; McTeague et al., 2011; Ball et al., 2012; Wangelin et al., 2012). At the same time, the crucial importance of art expertise for esthetic processing has been amply documented (e.g., Pihko et al., 2011; Leder et al., 2012; Pang et al., 2013; Else et al., 2015). Based on these and other findings, we suggest that the individual profile of empathic response to a work of art will depend on the interaction of five factors: first, the individual characteristics of the subject (including his/her age, gender, parenthood, his/her role as caregiver etc., and previous experience with depicted pain or misfortune); second, the subject's dispositional empathy (Davis, 1983), defined as the viewer's responsiveness to the observed experiences of others, has been found to correlate with the frequency and magnitude of empathic response (Davis, 1996; Avenanti et al., 2009); third, the subject's cultural-cognitive competence in relation to the experiential situation; fourth, the intergroup empathy bias, that is, the perceived closeness and relationship to the person or people depicted; and fifth, the momentary psychosomatic state of the observer. The critical among these variables are dispositional empathy and cultural-cognitive competence.

The culture-cognitive competence, which we take to be broader in scope than “expertise,” incorporating experience, skills and knowledge related to viewing art works and making sense of cultural products, may be the most important personal characteristic. Both the viewing of art and empathy (in some descriptions) are a type of skill, and in the experience of art they mutually reinforce each other. Importantly, higher cultural-cognitive competence (Kesner, 2006) need not correlate with a stronger empathic response and may in fact prove constraining and inhibit the empathic response. The viewer's knowledge that (s)he is looking at a masterpiece by an acknowledged artistic genius and her culturally-ingrained expectations vis-à-vis such a great work of art—for example, that one's experience should primarily be one of wonder at and appreciation of the artistic accomplishment, rather than a direct, bodily-mediated reaction—will likely affect the patterns of scanning and attentional allocation (e.g., prioritizing visual-semantic saliences related to esthetic meaning over affective affordances), thus circumventing and down-regulating the development of imminent, bodily-mediated reactions. In a similar vein, if the viewer's mind is focusing on an art-historical interpretation of the intended message of the painting (e.g., to offer an insight into biblical metaphor when Samson's suffering is to be understood as opening the path to his redemption, and blindness becomes a prerequisite for spiritual vision; see Perlove and Silver, 2009, p.113) this semantic knowledge may strongly modulate the empathic reaction in the sense of a down-regulation and reappraisal of affective feelings for Samson as the victim of horrendous mutilation. In an optimal scenario, the developed skills of viewing and making sense of art allow a flexibility of response response, which can range between empathy-related and esthetic aspects of experience (as we detail in section An Integrated Model of Empathy-Related Responses to Figural Artworks).

The Role of the Representational Medium and the Reality-Effect in Empathic Response

Current accounts of the empathic response to art do not sufficiently consider the crucial role played by the mediating effect of the representational medium. However, any comprehensive account of empathic response to art needs to take into account how the contextual and relational modulation of empathic response is realized vis-à-vis the interaction of the viewer with the particular medium of representation. To begin with, there is an obvious difference between the response to an observed real event unfolding before the subject and a depicted event.3 Observing representation provides a different set of affordances for the viewer's engagement than being present at the scene of real-life suffering. Consequently, every visual image modulates the empathic response by the simple fact of its being decoupled from the here and now of actually observing an event live, and this is true even in the case of live TV or online broadcasting. Interestingly, this distinction was already taken for granted a long time ago by medieval theologians, who argued that the image might be a more efficient model and stimulus for spiritual movement than the observed behavior of living people (Jezler, 1983).

Perhaps the key question related to our topic here concerns the problem of to what extent the capacity of an artistic or a non-artistic image to elicit an empathic response depends on the viewer's belief in the psychological reality of the depicted event—of the presence of real or fictional characters and the reality of their pain and suffering. This “reality effect” is related to the phenomenon of immersion or absorption in fiction, defined as a vicarious experiencing of events and emotions in fictional representation as if they were real (Walton, 1990; Oatley, 1999). Links between fictional narratives provided by texts, cinema or computer games and empathy have been extensively discussed (e.g., Coplan, 2004; Mar and Oatley, 2008; Mar et al., 2011; Tamir et al., 2016). As Oatley (1999) points out, a prerequisite for the development of empathic skills is emotional transportation into the story. The narrative itself acts to evoke and transform emotions, both directly through the events and characters depicted and (indirectly) through the cueing of emotionally valenced memories. Once evoked by the story, these emotions can in turn influence a person's experience of the narrative (Mar et al., 2011). To be effective, a narrative world has to be real within its context in order to instigate imaginative projections (Green, 2004; Bal and Veltkamp, 2013), that is, the ability to experience the narrative depends on the viewer's subjective feeling of being a witness to the depicted scene. Related evidence suggests that subjects' emotional reactions to unpleasant images as indexed by psychophysiological parameters are attenuated if the subjects perceive the depicted scenes as fictitious instead of real (Mocaiber et al., 2010, 2011). On the other hand, we submit that empathic response does not require that the viewer identify with the depicted character (a detailed discussion of the identification aspect is beyond the scope of this paper, but for a discussion of identification with characters in literature, see Zillmann, 1994; Keen, 2006).

However, the specific role played by different visual media in staging the reality effect or witness perspective for the beholder remains little understood. In some cases, the viewer's implicit belief in the mimetic transparency of the medium elicits in her a subjective sense of being a witness to the depicted scene. Thus, for the observer of medieval images the painting may have had roughly the kind of documentary value that photographic or video-documentary images do for viewers today. Historical evidence suggests that religious images (augmented by narratives) often served to transport the viewer into the time and space of the depicted event or even to change his/her status from that of a viewer to that of a participant (e.g., Lentes, 2000). Such transient immersion in the fictional world likely intensified the empathic response. To make matters more complicated, however, the adoption of a witness perspective may, or in other instances may not, be related to the degree of verisimilitude (“realism”) with which the medium presents the depicted characters and events. No direct correlation can be established between the phenomenally felt vividness of the depicted event for the viewer and the realism of the image-vehicle. That much is suggested by neuroimaging studies on empathy for pain or social pain that utilized distinctly unnaturalistic stimuli such as computer-generated figures (Masten et al., 2011; Meyer et al., 2013, 2015) or sketches (Krach et al., 2011), yet caused participants to perceive others as active, salient, and significant persons. Other experiments using low-fidelity computer avatars confirm that subjects are capable of interacting with them on phenomenal, behavioral and neuronal levels as if they were real, despite their cognitive knowledge that they are not (Slater et al., 2006; Cheetham et al., 2009). Slater et al.'s observation (2006: p. 6) that the perceptual and neural mechanisms that underlie such a response are largely unexplored still holds true. Thus, manifestly unrealistic (stylized) works of art that proclaim their status as fiction may have the ability to stage a reality effect for a viewer in a particular observational context and trigger an empathic response as effectively as do media that are perceived as providing documentary evidence. On the other hand, there is some evidence that the empathic response to visual stimuli does to some extent depend on the modality through which the image is conveyed. Several studies comparing empathic reactions, measured as the brain activity in subjects observing painful situations in photographs and cartoons, concluded that the neural activity linked to empathy for pain decreased when the reality of the painful stimuli was reduced by presenting painful stimulation in cartoon form (Han et al., 2005; Gu and Han, 2007). Similar results were recently obtained for moving images, where neuronal correlates of emotional empathy were observed in (viewers of) live-action movies, but not in (viewers of) animated movies (Vemuri and Surampudi, 2015). Further elucidating the relationship between the behavioral and neuronal indices of empathic response to the image and the reality effect subjectively perceived by the viewer clearly remains a major goal for future research.

An Integrated Model of Empathy-Related Responses to Figural Artworks

While neuroimaging research on empathy typically focuses on isolating empathic response to visual (or other) stimuli, the empathy-related response to visual art work does not, as a rule, occur in isolation but is embedded within the overall experience or the making sense of an image. Therefore, it is necessary to consider how empathic response is related to the overall experience of the viewer—both in a naturalistic and in an experimental setting. We begin by briefly contrasting a response to a work of art vs. a non-artistic image. Empathic concern and response is generally taken as a precursor and motivation for prosocial, altruistic behavior (Batson, 1991; Preston and de Waal, 2002) and much recent research has focused on investigating the perception-action cascade in empathy (e.g., Mathur et al., 2010; Masten et al., 2011; Zanon et al., 2014). When a person observes non-artistic images (such as media representations) of suffering, the empathic distress elicited by the depicted pain and misfortune of real people may translate into empathic concern and ultimately to some form of prosocial or altruistic behavior: the viewer donates money or tries in some other way to alleviate the ordeal of the depicted victims. Making sense of the image has thus an other-directed prosocial behavior as a tangible output (for a good example of this, see Lieberman, 2013, p. 151–152). On the other hand, when art works are viewed in a museum, this tight coupling of perception and action does not occur, no imminent behavioral reaction to the pain or the negative emotions of the depicted figures is produced. Shaun Gallagher describes the embodied response to art works as an “affordance short-circuit,” which is “. a kinaesthetic-anticipatory response to a non-realizable (non-practical, non-interactionable) affordance, .…an opportunity for experience of the purely possible or maybe even the impossible” (Gallagher, 2011, p. 108–109). How can the embedding of the empathic response within the broader art experience be conceptualized?4 We would argue that the experience of empathy-eliciting figural art works prompts a dynamic and fluctuating interaction between two interlinked sets of processes: socio-affective/cognitive processing, related to the person perception, which includes one or more domains of empathy and the theory of mind (Blakemore and Frith, 2003; Lieberman, 2007; Ochsner, 2008; Adolphs, 2010; Freeman et al., 2012; Stanley and Adolphs, 2013), and esthetic processing, primarily concerned with esthetic appreciation and the judgment of and attention to non-social aspects of the image. Unlike the naturalistic socio-emotional cognition of people, which is typically based on the integration of multimodal cues, (Freeman et al., 2012; Zaki, 2013), here the cues (or affordances) are unimodal, that is, visual. Rather than integrating multimodal cues, an encounter with a figural work of art allows the viewer to focus on the deeper processing offered by a single (visual) modality. In a figural depiction, any affective/social affordance enacted by a painting or sculpture at the same time offers itself as an artistic/esthetic affordance.

A Model of Empathy within Art Experience

Having discussed several critical factors relating to empathic response to figural depiction, we now turn to outlining an integrated model of empathy-related response to figural art work. We present it as a heuristic device that seeks to organize the multiplicity of factors that determine emphatic response and to capture the embedding of empathy-related response within the broader art (pictorial) experience. The model represents—in a necessarily abstract manner—the engagement of a viewer with both original figural art work and its reproduction in either a private viewing situation or an experimental setting (Figure 3).

The model is envisioned as functioning as follows:

• The viewer, with his or her distinct combination of dispositions (including, most importantly, dispositional empathy and cultural-cognitive competence, see Section Personal Factors Modulating the Empathic Response to Works of Art) engages with a work of art in a specific spatial-experiential context. The context modulates how the empathic response unfolds within the overall art experience by creating the spatial constraints of viewing, imposing cultural associations and especially by providing the semantic framework (mostly various forms of top-down priming conditions) of the perceptual encounter (as discussed above Section Contextual Framing: Pictorial, Spatial-Experiential, and Cultural Contexts).

• The specific pattern of interaction (i) between different empathy-related mechanisms and (ii) between socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing as the experience unfolds is simultaneously co-determined by the specific features of the image. These include: the presentation format, the placement of the figures within the (pictorial) composition (2D images), or the viewing space (3D images), the specific configuration of emotional body clues (gestures, postures), the depicted action, the arousal and valence of emotion embodied by the figure(s), the presence/absence of eye contact with the figure(s), the degree of verisimilitude (realism) and the relative prominence of particular aspects of the representational medium (color, materiality, brushwork etc.). Predictably, other factors being equal, such image characteristics alone may strongly affect the specific patterns of response on a psychological and neural level. Thus, paintings like Blinding, with its dynamic composition of figures and its depiction of bodily mutilation, pain and violent action, will be likely to elicit motor empathy and affective pain empathy that are mediated by a pain matrix and action-observation (or mirror) network. On the other hand, as recent experimental evidence suggests, portraits of subjects with emotional expressions who establish eye contact with the viewer /Figure 4/ are more likely to elicit affective empathy and mentalizing (Kesner et al. submitted). Likewise, the relative prominence of the medium at the expense of the realism of the depicted figures may weaken the empathic response. Importantly, all the key variables co-determining the course and magnitude of the empathic response (especially semantic priming, and features of the images) can be experimentally manipulated, thus allowing for empirical testing of the model.

• The relative magnitude of the empathy-related process and the interaction between socio-affective and esthetic processing is from the inception of the perceptual encounter further modulated by the features of the viewer's unfolding response: his/her implicit belief in the reality of the depicted event (or the witness perspective, as discussed in Section The Role of the Representational Medium and the Reality-Effect in Empathic Response), the viewer's like/dislike of the protagonists and understanding of the depicted scene or plot. The interaction between socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing as a key aspect of the model is further explored below (Patterns of Interaction between Socio-Affective/Cognitive and Esthetic Processing).

• While none of the factors listed in the diagram in isolation constitutes a necessary or sufficient condition for empathic response to occur, the co-occurrence of key factors will in most cases be a sufficient condition for the empathic response to develop. As a critical feature we single out priming by narratives (or by task/procedure in experimental condition among contextual factors and the presence of highly salient emotional cues in the image, along with direct gaze and effects of the medium that help to enact a witness perspective in a viewer's mind. Depending on their particular combination, the specific pattern of processing ensues, which may take the form of a learned or ritualized “action script” or highly individual, even idiosyncratic response.

• One or more modes of empathic engagements (kinesthetic-motor resonance, affective sharing, cognitive empathy, compassion) depend on and are intertwined with a multitude of other psychological mechanisms, subserving both socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing. These involve both reflexive (automatic) and reflective (controlled, volitional, and effortful) processes:

• Finally, while our focus here has been on response to works of art, the model equally applies to response to other empathy-eliciting depictions with non-art status that are circulating in the wider visual culture. For instance, viewing multiple representations of suffering in the media that are primarily intended to communicate information and elicit emotional/empathic reactions in their viewers /Figure 5/ may likewise involve an esthetic appraisal, whereby there occurs an interaction between socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. A model of empathy-related response to figural art work. Underlined text indicates the critical factors. Double arrows in the rightmost box indicate the bi-directional interaction between socio affective/cognitive and esthetic processing.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. Zbyněk Sekal, Self-portrait, drawing, 1946. With kind permission of Arbor Vitae Publishers.

FIGURE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 5. Filip Singer, from a series Migration Crisis-Lesbos, 2015. With kind permission of the author.

Patterns of Interaction between Socio-Affective/Cognitive and Esthetic Processing

As described (above), it is always the specific interaction of given image characteristics, personal and contextual factors, as outlined above, that determines the mutual bi-directional interaction between socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processes for the duration of the encounter. In some situations one of the two responses (affective/empathy-related vs. esthetic) may prevail and dominate the experience. An example would be the case of a medieval audience responding emotionally to scenes of the Passion of Christ discussed above, or instances of people talking to portraits, or of people being sexually aroused by statues (Pygmalionism). There is ample (and psychologically relevant) evidence from art history and criticism, anthropology and literature testifying to the occurrence of various affective and sexual responses to depicted persons as if they were real. In the case of sculpture in particular the encounter is often intercorporeal, intersubjective and reactive (Stoichita, 2008; Getsy, 2014). What works of art afford is the possibility to switch—within a focused and sustained viewing experience—between the first-person, observational stance and second-person interactive engagement. At the opposite extreme, the experience of images such as Blinding, which manifestly solicit an embodied empathic understanding, may in some cases proceed on the level of an appreciation of the work's formal and semantic qualities, without any affective-empathic response. In the case of modern-day viewers, many encounters with empathy-eliciting artworks are probably too brief and superficial for the experience to be able to develop significantly along either trajectory, so that it remains limited to a basic semantic understanding of what the work depicts (as discussed in Kesner, 2014). In the optimal scenario, however, an ongoing encounter with a complex, empathy-eliciting artwork produces a looping or “seesaw” effect, in which the dominance of one aspect gives way to the dominance of another, and they support each other in a mutually reinforcing cycle.

Importantly, our model does not assume that the empathic response develops along any fixed trajectory from affective resonance to cognitively mediated understanding. There is no behavioral evidence for the presumed automaticity of embodied simulation in viewing artworks and no default direction for empathic reaction from (what embodied simulation theorists label) “automatic empathic response as a basic level of response” (Freedberg and Gallese, 2007) to cognitively elaborated empathizing with the situation of the depicted persons should be posited. Observing museum visitors suggests that if anything like an “automatic” or “basic level of” response to a work of art (on the automatic processing in cognition, see Moors and De Houwer, 2006) can be postulated in relation to viewing a work of art, then that response has to do with the perceptual and semantic understanding of the image—recognizing/identifying the subject and conceptually labeling the depicted scene and persons or event. On the contrary, as subjective accounts of experiences suggest, often there is a gradual process of conscious making sense of or coming to terms with the image that extends over a protracted period of viewing, which then opens the possibility for a full-blown empathic response that ultimately incorporates bodily affective resonance, imaginative projection, and feelings of distress and/or sympathy and compassion.

The mutual interaction of socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing can proceed in a number of ways, for example (i) when the viewer shifts his/her attention from the depicted human targets to other aspects of the composition (as described above in the case study of Blinding)—such attention shifting can be experimentally ascertained by eye-tracking measurements); or (ii) when the viewer encounters depicted faces and bodies that elicit empathy-related responses and are at the same time esthetically appraised as being beautiful or ugly (cf. as quoted above with reference to the Blinding of Samson: “Apart from the revolting realism of the actual blinding, every detail, every hand and foot, is ugly in itself”.; for an esthetic appraisal of human bodies, cf. Martín-Loeches et al., 2014; Candidi and Aglioti, 2015); or (iii) when the affective/empathic response to the depicted figures and the esthetic appraisal of the picture as a whole proceeds in a bi-directional exchange or continuous loop. For instance, the very formation of an “emotion percept,” which in real-life social vision involves the rapid integration of compound social cues (Adams and Kveraga, 2015; Marchi and Newen, 2015), will in pictorial perception often evolve into an esthetic appraisal that is concerned with detecting and analyzing incongruences between compound social-emotional cues, such as facial expression, gaze, bodily posture, and gesture (such ambiguities often constituting the artistic intention of the image). Once formed, a cognitively elaborated emotion-percept will stimulate further esthetic appraisal, or it will trigger an empathic resonance in the viewer.

Furthermore, in images that present scenes of one or more interacting figures but offer no direct clue as to the nature of their relationship or the meaning of the pictured event, it is mostly the intentional operation of understanding the circumstances of depicted persons as a necessary precondition for affective resonance and embodied empathic understanding (in both its aspects, i.e., feeling as and feeling for the depicted target). In such cases, it is the viewer's access to some sort of extra-pictorial semantic information and the grasp of the meaning of the depicted situation that both prompts mental simulation and provides clues that lead to a deeper emotional/empathic processing (for a case study of this process in a specific work of art, see Kesner, 2014). Furthermore, as Zillmann (1991) suggested, empathy may be mediated by morally derived affective dispositions toward the target, which again argues against the notion that the empathic response to an image automatically takes precedence Art-historical/critical literature (which, as a rule, continues to be ignored by neuroesthetics research) and literary sources contain a massive amount of revealing evidence of the existence of this kind of “seesaw” effect, a shifting awareness between being confronted with a (depicted) human person and being confronted with an esthetic object (e.g., Herder, 1778; Riegl, 1902; Steinberg, 1988; Stoichita, 2008; Sidlauskas, 2009 to cite some very different examples).

Secondly, in a deep encounter with an empathy-eliciting art work, empathic distress (feeling like the depicted persons) and compassion (feeling for them) will be typically accompanied by a range of mental states that add to the phenomenological complexity of the experience of art. Depending on the particular work of art and the interaction of factors described in the model, (these mental states) may include basic emotions and complex affective states, such as being moved (Hanich et al., 2014), “feeling like crying” (Pelowski, 2015) or morbid fascination (Oosterwijk et al., 2016), but they can also include specific esthetic emotions. Negative emotions and empathic distress, although subjectively felt as something disquieting and distressing, may ultimately be consciously reappraised in positive terms so that the entire experience is remembered as enjoyable (the “enjoyment of tragedy” phenomenon, cf. De Wied et al., 1994) and transformative (Pelowski and Akiba, 2011), hence rewarding and motivating further encounters of this kind. This process of making sense of the image can be productively considered in relation to the constructivist theories of emotional perception and experience (Russell, 2003), and in particular the model of situated conceptualization (Barrett and Satpute, 2013; Barrett, 2015; see also Minissale, 2013: p. 104–06).

Future Challenges

Given the phenomenological and psychological complexity of the empathy-related responses that are an inherent part of art experience and the manifold factors that co-determine the specific course of the experience, two important questions arise: (i) how is the proposed interaction of socio-cognitive and esthetic processing instantiated by brain structures, and (ii) can the model be experimentally verified? The imminent challenge, then, is to develop experimental neuroimaging paradigms for investigating the interaction of socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing, under different variables of task conditions/context modulations, image characteristics and personal profiles of subjects.5 For instance, our preliminary results from an ongoing pilot study suggest that by emulating semantic priming in naturalistic conditions by providing viewers with specific viewing instructions aimed at guiding their attention either to the subjects and the emotions elicited by the subjects in the observer, or to the representational and artistic features of the work, it is possible to isolate distinct patterns of neuronal activity related to either socio-affective/cognitive or esthetic processing. Furthermore, as it is recognized that the temporal dynamics of the neuronal activity that underlies both affective (empathic) and esthetic experience may be as important as the spatial distribution of the activity (Immordino-Yang et al., 2009; Adolphs, 2010; Cela-Conde and Ayala, 2015; Betti and Aglioti, 2016; Kirsch et al., 2016), a major methodological challenge is to find ways of combining and integrating the data drawn from high spatial resolution (fMRI) with “fast” electrocortical data. Another challenge, to recap what has already been noted, concerns the possibility of experimentally verifying the role of the subjectively perceived reality effect—that is, the degree to which the subject's sense that the depicted figures and events are real (a sense generated both by the characteristics of a representational medium (as such) and by task condition) impacts the magnitude and specific profile of the empathic response.

Finally, the view of empathic response that we embraced here highlights the crucial importance of subjectively felt, conscious experience. As Lamm and Majdandžic (2015) recently pointed out, methods such as fMRI only provide information on neural responses that co-occur with the experience of empathy. While this point may seem self-evident, it is worth emphasizing that any experimental research on empathic response to art that does not attempt to correlate or integrate objective data with first-person reports on subjective experience will provide a greatly limited and constrained view of the phenomenon, such as could be of little interest to scholars outside the neurosciences and certainly would not foster much needed truly interdisciplinary research efforts. We therefore conclude that the greatest general challenge lies in developing experimental paradigms that would permit correlating and integrating data on the neuronal indices of empathic responses to images with behavioral indices and with narrative first-person accounts of empathic response and experience.

Author Contributions

LK developed the structure and main theoretical aspects and has written substantial parts of the paper. JH contributed to the theoretical model and writing of the paper.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The work is a result of the research funded by the project No. LO1611 with financial support from the Ministry of Education, Youth and Sport under the NPU I program and by the Czech Science Foundation (GA CR) grant no. 15-08577S “Affective response in the visual arts: linking art history and neuroscience perspectives”. The authors would like to thank Tereza Nekovárová and Yuliya Zatyseva for their comments and Petr Adámek for assistance with the bibliography and illustrations.

Footnotes

1. ^In discussing “the affectivity condition” (for empathy to occur), Shaun Gallagher highlights the inherent difficulties involved in specifying[determining] the affective state of the observer of a person suffering (Gallagher, 2012, 374–375). We follow Decety and Jackson's (2004, 73) view that an affective response to another person (as one of the principal components of empathy) often, but not always, entails sharing that person's affective state. However, a more comprehensive discussion of this point is beyond the scope of this article.

2. ^Here we take the standard definition of social pain as painful feelings arising from social rejection, exclusion, or loss of a loved one (see Eisenberg, 2015 for a review).

3. ^In neuroimaging experiments based on “direct observation” of painful stimuli delivered to the bodies of other people or painful social situations affecting other people, the (response) effect invariably occurs when the viewer is presented with photographs, video clips, or other graphic materials, which are intrinsically assumed to be transparent media that straightforwardly present the event as if it were real. In fact, however, such experiments cannot be said to assess the psychological and neuronal dimension of the reaction involved in “witnessing live a painful event” or “directly witnessing a live person,” as they claim to do (Bruneau et al., 2012).

4. ^Here we maintain the important distinction between related, yet conceptually distinct notions of art experience and esthetic experience (Palmer et al., 2013). For the purpose of the present discussion we take “esthetic processing” to refer to a range of cognitive and affective mechanisms as detailed below.

5. ^We acknowledge, but do not further discuss here, the methodological difficulties of isolating specific socio-affective/cognitive and esthetic processing. As noted by Adolphs (2010, 761), the distinction between social and nonsocial is always introduced by the experimenter.

References

Adams, R. B., and Kveraga, K. (2015). Social vision: functional forecasting and the integration of compound social cues. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 6, 591–610. doi: 10.1007/s13164-015-0256-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Adolphs, R. (2010). Conceptual challenges and directions for social neuroscience. Neuron 65, 752–767. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2010.03.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ando, A., Salatino, A., Giromini, L., Ricci, R., Pignolo, C., Cristofanelli, S., et al. (2015). Embodied simulation and ambiguous stimuli: the role of the mirror neuron system. Brain Res. 1629, 135–142. doi: 10.1016/j.brainres.2015.10.025

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Auvray, M., Myin, E., and Spence, C. (2010). The sensory-discriminative and affective- motivational aspects of pain. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 34, 214–223. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2008.07.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Avenanti, A., Minio-Paluello, I., Bufalari, I., and Aglioti, S. M. (2009). The pain of a model in the personality of an onlooker: influence of state-reactivity and personality traits on embodied empathy for pain. NeuroImage 44, 275–283. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.08.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baird, A. D., Scheffer, I. E., and Wilson, S. J. (2011). Mirror neuron system involvement in empathy: a critical look at the evidence. Soc. Neurosci. 6, 327–335. doi: 10.1080/17470919.2010.547085

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bal, P. M., and Veltkamp, M. (2013). How does fiction reading influence empathy? An experimental investigation on the role of emotional transportation. PLoS ONE 8:e55341. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0055341

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ball, T. M., Sullivan, S., Flagan, T., Hitchcock, C. A., Simmons, A., Paulus, M. P., et al. (2012). Selective effects of social anxiety, anxiety sensitivity, and negative affectivity on the neural bases of emotional face processing. NeuroImage 59, 1879–1887. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.08.074

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F. (2015). “The conceptual act theory: a road map,” in The Psychological Construction of Emotion, eds L. F. Barett and J. A. Russell (New York, NY: The Guildford Publications), 83–110.

Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F., Mesquita, B., and Gendron, M. (2011). Context in emotion perception. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 20, 286–290. doi: 10.1177/0963721411422522

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F., and Satpute, A. B. (2013). Large-scale brain networks in affective and social neuroscience: towards an integrative functional architecture of the brain. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 23, 361–372. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2012.12.012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Batson, C. D. (1991). The Altrusim Question. Toward a Social Psychological Answer. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Google Scholar

Batson, C. D. (2009). “These things called empathy: eight related but distinct phenomena,” in The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, eds J. Decety and W. Ickes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 3–15.

Google Scholar

Bebko, G. M., Franconeri, S. L., Ochsner, K. N., and Chiao, J. Y. (2011). Look before you regulate: differential perceptual strategies underlying expressive suppression and cognitive reappraisal. Emotion 11, 732–742. doi: 10.1037/a0024009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Belting, H. (1981). Das Bild und sein Publikum im Mittelalter. Form und Funktion früher Bildtafeln der Passion. Berlin: Gebr. Mann Verlag.

Google Scholar

Bennett, J. (2001). Stigmata and sense memory: St. Francis and the affective image. Art Hist. 24, 1–16. doi: 10.1111/1467-8365.00247

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bergeron, V., and Lopes, D. (2014). “Aesthetic theory and aesthetic science: prospects for integration,” in Aesthetic Science. Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience, eds A. Shimamura and S. Palmer (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 63–79.

Bernhardt, B. C., and Singer, T. (2012). The neural basis of empathy. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 35, 1–23. doi: 10.1146/annurev-neuro-062111-150536

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Betti, V., and Aglioti, S. (2016). Dynamic construction of the neural networks underpinning empathy for pain. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 63, 191–206. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.02.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Blakemore, S.-J., and Frith, U. (2003). How does the brain deal with the social world? Neuroreport 15, 119–128. doi: 10.1097/00001756-200401190-0002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brieber, D., Nadal, M., and Leder, H. (2015). In the white cube: Museum context enhances the valuation and memory of art. Acta Psychol. 154, 36–42. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2014.11.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brieber, D., Nadal, M., Leder, H., and Rosenberg, R. (2014). Art in time and space: context modulates the relation between art appreciation and viewing time. PLoS ONE 9:e99019. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0099019

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bruneau, E. G., Pluta, A., and Saxe, R. (2012). The role of the ‘shared pain’ and ‘theory of mind’ networks in processing others' emotional suffering. Neuropsychologia 50, 219–231. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2011.11.008

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bullot, N. J., and Reber, R. (2013). The Artful Mind Meets Art History: toward a psycho-historical framework for the science of art appreciation. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 123–137. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12000489

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Calder, A. J., Ewbank, M., and Passamonti, L. (2011). Personality influences the neural responses to viewing facial expressions of emotion. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 366, 1684–1701. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2010.0362

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Candidi, M., and Aglioti, S. (2015). Visual and sensorimotor contributions to the esthetic appraisal of body form, motion and emotion. Eur. Psychol. 20, 16–26. doi: 10.1027/1016-9040/a000221

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Caramazza, A., Anzellotti, S., Strnad, L., and Lingnau, A. (2014) Embodied cognition mirror neurons: a critical assessment. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 37, 1–15. doi: 10.1146/annurev-neuro-071013-013950

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casati, R., and Pignocchi, A. (2007). Mirror and canonical neurons are not constitutive of aesthetic responses. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11:411. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2007.07.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cela-Conde, C., and Ayala, F. (2015). “Art and brain co-evolution,” in Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain. eds J. Huston, M. Nadal, F. Mora, L. Agnati, and C. Cela-Conde (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 408–425.

Google Scholar

Cheetham, M., Pedroni, A. F., Antley, A., Slater, M., and Jäncke, L. (2009). Virtual milgram: empathic concern or personal distress? Evidence from functional MRI and dispositional measures. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 3:29. doi: 10.3389/neuro.09.029.2009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, K. (1966). Rembrandt and the Italian Renaissance. London: Murray.

Google Scholar

Clarke, E., DeNora, T., and Vuoskoski, J. (2015). Music, empathy and cultural understanding. Phys. Life Rev. 15, 61–88. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2015.09.001.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coplan, A. (2004). Empathic engagement with narrative fictions. J. Aesthet. Art Criticism 62, 141–152. doi: 10.1111/j.1540-594X.2004.00147.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coplan, A., and Goldie, P. (Eds.) (2011). Empathy. Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Cox, C. L., Uddin, L. Q., Di Martino, A., Castellanos, F. X., Milham, M. P., and Kelly, C. (2012). The balance between feeling and knowing: affective and cognitive empathy are reflected in the brain's intrinsic functional dynamics. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 7, 727–737. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsr051

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cuff, B., Brown, S. J., Taylor, L., and Howat, D. (2014). Empathy: a review of the concept. Emotion Rev. 8, 144–153. doi: 10.1177/1754073914558466

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Curtis, R., and Koch, G. (2009). Einfühlung: Zu Geschichte und Gegenwart Eines Ästhetischen Konzepts. München: Wilhelm Fink.

Davies, D. (2014). “‘This is your brain on art’: what can philosophy of art learn from neuroscience?,” in Aesthetics and The Sciences of Mind, eds G. Currie, M. Kieran, A. Meskin, and J. Robson (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 57–74.

Google Scholar

Davis, M. H. (1983). Measuring individual differences in empathy: evidence for a multidimensional approach. J. Person. Soc. Psychol. 44, 113–126.

Google Scholar

Davis, M. H. (1996). Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

Google Scholar

Decety, J. (2010a). The neurodevelopment of empathy in humans. Dev. Neurosci. 32, 257–267. doi: 10.1159/000317771

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J. (2010b). To what extend is the experience of empathy mediated by shared neural circuits? Emotion Rev. 2, 204–207. doi: 10.1177/1754073910361981

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J. (2011). Dissecting the neural mechanisms mediating empathy. Emotion Rev. 3, 92–108. doi: 10.1177/1754073910374662

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J., and Jackson, P. (2004). The functional architecture of human empathy. Behav. Cogn. Neurosci. Rev. 3, 71–100. doi: 10.1177/1534582304267187

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Decety, J., and Meyer, M. (2008). From emotion resonance to empathic understanding: A social developmental neuroscience account. Dev. Psychopathol. 20, 1053–1080. doi: 10.1017/S0954579408000503

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

De Greck, M., Wang, G., Yang, X., Wang, X., Northoff, G., and Han, S. (2012). Neural substrates underlying intentional empathy. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 7, 135–144. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsq093

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

De Vignemont, F., and Jacob, P. (2012). What is it like to feel another's pain? Philos. Sci. 79, 295–316. doi: 10.1086/664742

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

De Wied, M., Zillmann, D., and Ordman, V. (1994). The role of empathic distress in the enjoyment of cinematic tragedy. Poetics 23, 91–106.

Google Scholar

Eisenberg, N. I. (2015). Social pain and the brain: controversies, questions, an where to go from here, Ann. Rev. Psychol. 66, 601–629. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115146

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Else, J. E., Ellis, J., and Orme, E. (2015). Art expertise modulates the emotional response to modern art, especially abstract: an ERP investigation. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9:525. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00525

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eres, R., and Molenberghs, P. (2013). The influence of group membership on the neural correlates involved in empathy. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7:176. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2013.00176

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Etkin, A., Klemenhagen, K., Dudman, J., Rogan, M., Hen, R., Kandel, E., et al. (2004). Individual differences in trait anxiety predict the response of the basolateral amygdala to unconsciously processed fearful faces. Neuron 44, 1043–1055. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2004.12.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fan, Y., Duncan, N. W., De Greck, M., and Northoff, G. (2011). Is there a core neural network in empathy? An fMRI based quantitative meta-analysis. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 35, 903–911. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2010.10.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Freedberg, D. (1989). The Power of Images. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Freedberg, D. (2007). “Empathy, motion and emotion,” in Wie Sich Gefühle Ausdruck Verschaffen: Emotionen in Nahsicht, eds K. Herding and A. Krause-Wahl. (Berlin: Driesen), 17–51.

Google Scholar

Freedberg, D. (2011). “Memory in art: history and the neuroscience of response,” in The Memory Process: Neuroscientific and Humanistic Perspectives, eds S. Nalbantian, P. Matthews, and J. McClelland (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 337–358.

Freedberg, D., and Gallese, V. (2007). Motion, emotion and empathy in esthetic experience. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11, 197–203. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2007.02.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Freeman, J. B., Johnson, K. L., Adams, R. B. Jr., and Ambady, N. (2012). The social-sensory interface: category interactions in person perception. Front. Integr. Neurosci. 6:81. doi: 10.3389/fnint.2012.00081

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fried, M. (2002). Menzel's Realism: Art and Embodiment in Nineteenth-Century. Berlin: New Haven; London: Yale University Press.

Google Scholar

Fuchs, T., and Koch, S. C. (2014). Embodied affectivity: on moving and being moved. Front. Psychol. 5:508. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00508

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallagher, S. (2011). “Aesthetics and kinaesthetics,” in Sehen und Handeln, eds H. Bredekamp and J. M. Krois (Berlin: Akademie Verlag), 99–113.

Google Scholar

Gallagher, S. (2012). Empathy, simulation, and narrative. Sci. Context 25, 355–381. doi: 10.1017/S0269889712000117

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallese, V. (2003). The roots of empathy: the shared manifold hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity. Psychopathology 36, 171–180. doi: 10.1159/000072786

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallese, V. (2010). “Mirror neurons and art,” in Art and the Senses, eds F. Bacci and D. Melcher (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 441–449.

Gallese, V., and Caruana, F. (2016). Embodied simulation. Beyond the expression/experience dualism of emotions. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 397–398. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallese, V., Keysers, C., and Rizzolatti, G. (2004). A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 396–403. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2004.07.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallese, V., and Sinigaglia, C. (2011). What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends Cogn. Sci. 15, 512–519. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2011.09.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gerger, G., Leder, H., and Kremer, A. (2014). Context effects on emotional and aesthetic evaluations of artwortks and IAPS pictures. Acta Psychol. 151, 174–183. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2014.06.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Getsy, D. (2014). Acts of stilness: statues, performativity, and passive resistance. Criticism 56, 1–20.

Google Scholar

Gonzalez-Liencres, C., Shamay-Tsoory, S. G., and Brüne, M. (2013). Towards a neuroscience of empathy: ontogeny, phylogeny, brain mechanisms, context and psychopathology. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 37, 1537–1548. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2013.05.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gopnik, B. (2014). “Aesthetic science and artistic knowledge,” in Aesthetic Science. Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience, eds A. Shimamura and S. Palmer (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 129–162.

Google Scholar

Graham, R., and LaBar, K. (2012). Neurocognitive mechanisms of gaze-expression interactions in face processing and social attention. Neuropsychologia 50, 553–566. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2012.01.019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Green, M. C. (2004). Transportation into narrative worlds. The role of prior knowledge and perceived realism. Discourse Processes 38, 247–266. doi: 10.1207/s15326950dp3802_5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gu, X., and Han, S. (2007). Attention and reality constraints on the neural processes of empathy for pain. Neuroimage 36, 256–267. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2007.02.025

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gutsell, J. N., and Inzlicht, M. (2012). Intergroup differences in the sharing of emotive states: neural evidence of an empathy gap. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 7, 596–603. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsr035

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hamburger, J. F. (1998). The Visual and the Visionary: Art and Female Spirituality in Late Medieval GERMANY. New York, NY: Zone Books.

Google Scholar

Han, S., Jiang, Y., Humphreys, G. W., Zhou, T., and Cai, P. (2005). Distinct neural substrates for the perception of real and virtual visual worlds. Neuroimage 24, 928–935. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.09.046

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hanich, J., Wagner, V., Shah, M., Jacobsen, T., and Menninghaus, W. (2014). Why we like to watch sad films. The pleasure of being moved in aesthetic experiences. Psychol. Aesthetics Creativity Arts 8, 130–143. doi: 10.1037/a0035690

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hein, G., and Singer, T. (2008). I feel how you feel but not always: the empathic brain and its modulation. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 18, 153–158. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2008.07.012

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Herder, J. G. (1778). Plastik. Einige Wahrnehmungen über Form und Gestalt aus Pygmalions Bildendem Traume. Leipzig: Breitkopf.

Hickok, G. (2013). Do mirror neurons subserve action understanding? Neurosci. Lett. 540, 56–58. doi: 10.1016/j.neulet.2012.11.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Humphrey, K., Underwood, G., and Lambert, T. (2012). Salience of the lambs: a test of the saliency map hypothesis with pictures of emotive objects. J. Vision 12, 1–15. doi: 10.1167/12.1.22

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ibañez, A., and Manes, F. (2012). Contextual social cognition and the behavioral variant of frontotemporal dementia, Neurology 24, 1354–1362. doi: 10.1212/WNL

CrossRef Full Text

Immordino-Yang, M. H., McColl, A., Damasio, H., and Damasio, A. (2009). Neural correlates of admiration and compassion. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106, 8021–8026. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0810363106

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jacobsen, T. (2006). Bridging the art and the sciences: a framework for the psychology of aesthetics. Leonardo 39, 155–162. doi: 10.1162/leon.2006.39.2.155

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jezler, P. (1983). “Bildwerke im Dienste der dramatischen Ausgestaltung der Osterliturgie – Befürworter und Gegner,” in Von der Macht der Bilder. Beitrage des C. I. H. A. -Kolloquiums Kunst und Reformation, ed E. Ullmann (Leipzig: Karl-Marx-Universität), 236–249.

Kandel, E. (2012). The Age of Insight: The Quest to Understand the Unconscious in Art, Mind, and Brain, from Vienna 1900 to the Present. New York, NY: The Random House.

Google Scholar

Kanske, P., Böckler, A., Trautwein, F.-M., and Singer, T. (2015). Dissecting the social brain: introducing the EmpaToM to reveal distinct neural networks and brain-behavior relations for empathy and Theory of Mind. Neuroimage 122, 6–19. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2015.07.082

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kapoula, Z., Daunys, G., Herbez, O., and Yang, Q. (2009). Effect of title on eye-movement exploration of Cubist painting by Fernand Léger. Perception 38, 479–491. doi: 10.1068/p6080

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keen, S. (2006). A theory of narrative empathy. Narrative 14, 207–236.

Google Scholar

Kesner, L. (2006). The role of cognitive competence in the art museum experience. Museum Manag. Curatorship 21, 4–19. doi: 10.1080/09647770600302101

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kesner, L. (2010). “Neuroaesthetics: real promise or real delusion?,” in The Aesthetic Dimension of Visual Culture, eds O. Dadejdík and J. Stejskal (Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing), 17–32.

Google Scholar

Kesner, L. (2014). The predictive mind and the experience of visual art work. Front. Psychol. 5:1417. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01417

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kesner, L. (2016). Against the affectless iconology of modern art. Umění/Art 64, 2–18.

Google Scholar

Keysers, C., and Gazzola, V. (2009). Expanding the mirror: vicarious activity for actions, emotions, and sensations. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 19, 666–671. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2009.10.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kirk, U., Skov, M., Hulme, O., Christensen, M., and Zeki, S. (2009). Modulation of aesthetic value by semantic context: an fMRI study. Neuroimage 44, 1125–1132. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.10.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kirsch, L. P., Urgesi, C., and Cross, E. S. (2016). Shaping and reshaping the aesthetic brain: Emerging perspectives on the neurobiology of embodied aesthetics. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 62, 56–68. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2015.12.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Klimecki, O. M., Leiberg, S., Lamm, C., and Singer, T. (2013). Functional neural plasticity and associated changes in positive affect after compassion training. Cerebral Cortex, 23, 1552–1561. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2015.12.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krach, S., Cohrs, J. C. H., de Echeverria Loebell, N. C., Kircher, T., Sommer, J., Jansen, A., et al. (2011). Your flaws are my pain: linking empathy to vicarious embarrassment, PLoS ONE 6:e18675. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0018675

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kret, M. E., Stekelenburg, J. J., Roelofs, K., and De Gelder, B. (2013). Perception of face and body expressions using electromyography, pupillometry and gaze measures. Front. Psychol. 4:28. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00028

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krois, J. (2011). “Enactivism and embodiment in picture acts. the chirality of images,” in John, M. Krois. Bildkörper und Körperschema: Schriften zur Verkörperungstheorie Ikonischer Formen, eds H. Bredekamp and M. Laischke (Berlin: Akademie Verlag), 272–289.

Krukar, J. (2014). Walk, look, remember: the influence of the gallery's spatial layout on human memory for an art exhibition. Behav. Sci. 4, 181–201. doi: 10.3390/bs4030181

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kunz, M., Lautenbacher, S., Leblanc, N., and Rainville, P. (2012). Are both the sensory and the affective dimensions of pain encoded in the face?. Pain 153, 350–358. doi: 10.1016/j.pain.2011.10.027

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lai, M.-C., Lombardo, M. V., Chakrabarti, B., Ecker, C., Sadek, S. A., Wheelwright, S. J., et al. (2012). Individual differences in brain structure underpin empathizing–systemizing cognitive styles in male adults. Neuroimage 61, 1347–1354. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.03.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lamm, C., and Majdandžic, J. (2015). The role of shared neural activations, mirror neurons, and morality in empathy – A critical comment. Neurosci. Res. 90, 15–24. doi: 10.1016/j.neures.2014.10.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lamm, C., Batson, C. D., and Decety, J. (2007a). The neural substrate of human empathy: effects of perspective-taking and cognitive appraisal. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 19, 42–58. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2007.19.1.42

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lamm, C., Nusbaum, H. C., Meltzoff, A. N., and Decety, J. (2007b). What are you feeling? Using functional magnetic resonance imaging to assess the modulation of sensory and affective responses during empathy for pain. PLoS ONE 2:e1292. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0001292

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lanzoni, S. (2012). Introduction: emotion and the Sciences: varieties of empathy in science, art and history. Sci. Context 25, 287–300. doi: 10.1017/S0269889712000105

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leder, H., Carbon, C., and Ripsas, A. (2006). Entitling art: influence of title information on understanding and appreciation of paintings. Acta Psychol. 121, 176–198. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2005.08.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leder, H., Gerger, G., Dressler, S. G., and Schabmann, A. (2012). How art is appreciated. Psychol. Aesthetics Creativity Arts 6, 1–10. doi: 10.1037/a0026396

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lentes, T. (2000). “Auf der Suche nach dem Ort des Gedächtnisses,” in Imagination und Wirklichkeit. Zum Verhältnis von Mentalen und Realen Bildern in der Frühen Neuzeit, eds K. Krüger and A. Nova (Mainz: Phillip von Zabern), 1–35.

Lidov, A. (2006). “Hierotopy. The creation of sacred spaces as a form of creativity and subject of cultural history,” in Hierotopy. Creation of Sacred Spaces in Byzantium and Medieval Russia, ed A. Lidov (Moscow: Progress-Tradition), 32–58.

Lieberman, M. (2007). Social cognitive neuroscience: a review of core processes. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 58, 259–289. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085654

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lieberman, M. (2013). Social. Why Our Brains Are Wired to Connect. New York, NY: Broadway Books.

Google Scholar

Lindquist, K. A., and Gendron, M. (2013). What's in a word? Language constructs emotion perception. Emotion Rev. 5, 66–71. doi: 10.1177/1754073912451351

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lipps, T. (1903). Einfühlung, innere nachahmung und organempfindung. Arch. Gesamte Psychol. 1, 465–519.

Google Scholar

Mar, R. A., Oatley, K., Djikic, M., and Mullin, J. (2011). Emotion and narrative fiction: interactive influences before, during, and after reading. Cogn. Emotion 25, 818–833. doi: 10.1080/02699931.2010.515151

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mar, R., and Oatley, K. (2008). The function of fiction is the abstraction and simulation of social experience. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 3, 173–192. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6924.2008.00073.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Marchi, F., and Newen, A. (2015). Cognitive penetrability and emotion recognition in human facial expressions. Front. Psychol. 6:828. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00828

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Martín-Loeches, M., Hernández-Tamames, J. A., Martín, A., and Urrutia, M. (2014). Beauty and ugliness in the bodies and faces of others: an fMRI study of person esthetic judgement. Neuroscience 26, 486–497. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroscience.2014.07.040

CrossRef Full Text

Massaro, D., Savazzi, F., Di Dio, C., Freedberg, D., Gallese, V., Gilli, G., et al. (2012). When art moves the eyes: a behavioral and eye-tracking study. PLoS ONE 7:e37285. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0037285

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Masten, C. L., Morelli, S. A., and Eisenberger, N. I. (2011). An fMRI investigation of empathy for ‘social pain’ and subsequent prosocial behaviour. Neuroimage 55, 381–388. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.11.060

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mathur, V. A., Harada, T., Lipke, T., and Chiao, J. Y. (2010). Neural basis of extraordinary empathy and altruistic motivation. Neuroimage 51, 1468–1475. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.03.025

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McTeague, L. M., Shumen, J. R., Wieser, M. J., Lang, P. J., and Keil, A. (2011). Social vision: sustained perceptual enhancement of affective facial cues in social anxiety. Neuroimage 54, 1615–1624. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.08.080

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meeren, H. K., van Heijnsbergen, C. C., and de Gelder, B. (2005). Rapid perceptual integration of facial expression and emotional body language. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102, 16518–16523. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0507650102

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Melloni, M., Lopez, V., and Ibanez, A. (2014). Empathy and contextual social cognition. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 14, 407–442. doi: 10.3758/s13415-013-0205-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meyer, M. L., Masten, C. L., Ma, Y., Wang, C., Shi, Z., Eisenberger, N. I., et al. (2013). Empathy for the social suffering of friends and strangers recruits distinct patterns of brain activation. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 8, 446–454. doi: 10.1093/scan/nss019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meyer, M. L., Masten, C. L., Ma, Y., Wang, C., Shi, Z., Eisenberger, N. I., et al. (2015). Differential neural activation to friends and strangers links interdependence to empathy. Culture Brain 3, 21–38. doi: 10.1007/s40167-014-0023-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mikulan, E. P., Reynaldo, L., and Ibánez, A. (2014). Homuncular mirrors: misunderstanding causality in embodied cognition. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:299. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00299

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Millis, K. (2001). Making meaning brings pleasure: the influence of titles on aesthetic experiences. Emotion 1, 320–329. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.1.3.320

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Minissale, G. (2013). The Psychology of Contemporary Art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Mitchell, R., and Phillips, L. (2015). The overlapping relationship between emotion perception and theory of mind. Neuropsychologia 70, 1–10. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2015.02.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mocaiber, I., Perakakis, P., Pereira, M. G., Pinheiro, W. M., Volchan, E., de Oliveira L., et al. (2011). Stimulus appraisal modulates cardiac reactivity to briefly presented mutilation pictures. Int. J. Psychophysiol. 81, 299–304. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2011.07.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mocaiber, I., Pereira, M. G., Erthal, F. S., Machado-Pinheiro, W., David, I. A., and Cagy, M. (2010). Fact or fiction? An event-related potential study of implicit emotion regulation. Neurosci. Lett. 476, 84–88. doi: 10.1016/j.neulet.2010.04.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moors, A., and De Houwer, J. (2006). Automaticity: a theoretical and conceptual analysis. Psycholl. Bull. 132, 297–326. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.132.2.297

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Niu, Y., Todd, R. M., and Anderson, A. K. (2012). Affective salience can reverse the effects of stimulus-driven salience on eye movements in complex scenes. Front. Psychol. 3:336. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00336

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Noguchi, Y., and Murota, M. (2013). Temporal dynamics of neural activity in an integration of visual and contextual information in an esthetic preference task. Neuropsychologia 51, 1077–1084. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oatley, K. (1999). Why fiction may be twice as true as fact: fiction as cognitive and emotional simulation. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 3, 101–117. doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.3.2.101

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ochsner, K. (2008). The social-emotional processing stream: five core constructs and their translational potential for schizophrenia and beyond. Biol. Psychiatry 64, 48–61. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.04.024

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ochsner, K. N., Ray, R. D., Cooper, J. C., Robertson, E. R., Chopra, S., Gabrieli, J. D., et al. (2004). For better or for worse: neural systems supporting the cognitive down-and up-regulation of negative emotion. Neuroimage 23, 483–499. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.06.030

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ogino, Y., Nemoto, H., Inui, K., Saito, S., Kakigi, R., and Goto, F. (2007). Inner experience of pain: imagination of pain while viewing images showing painful events forms subjective pain representation in human brain. Cereb. Cortex 17, 1139–1146. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhl023

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oosterwijk, S., Lindquist, K. A., Adebayo, M., and Barrett, L. F. (2016). The neural representation of typical and atypical experiences of negative images: comparing fear, disgust and morbid fascination. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 11, 11–22. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsv088

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Palmer, S., Schloss, K., and Sammartino, J. (2013). Visual Aesthetics and Human Preference Ann. Rev. Psychol. 64, 77–107. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-120710-100504

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pang, C., Nadal, M., Müller-Paul, J., Rosenberg, R., and Klein, C. (2013). Electrophysiological correlates of looking at paintings and its association with art expertise. Biol. Psychol. 93, 246–254. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2012.10.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Papoulias, C., and Callard, F. (2010). Biology's gift: interrogating the turn to affect. Body Soc. 16, 29–56. doi: 10.1177/1357034X09355231

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pelowski, M. (2015) Tears transformation: feeling like crying as an indicator of insightful or “aesthetic” experience with art. Front. Psychol. 6:1006. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01006.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pelowski, M., and Akiba, F. (2011). A model of art perception, evaluation and emotion in transformative aesthetic experience. New Ideas Psychol. 29, 80–97. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.04.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Perlove, S., and Silver, L. (2009). Rembrandt's Faith: Church and Temple in the Dutch Golden Age. University Park, PA: The Penn State Press.

Google Scholar

Pihko, E., Virtanen, A., Saarinen, V., Pannasch, S., Hirvenkari, L., Tossavainen, T., et al. (2011) Experiencing art: the influence of expertise painting abstraction level. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 5:94. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2011.00094

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Preston, S. D., and de Waal, F. (2002). Empathy: its ultimate and proximate bases. Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 1–20. discussion: 20–71.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Price, D. D. (2000). Psychological and neural mechanisms of the affective dimension of pain. Science 288, 1769–1772. doi: 10.1126/science.288.5472.1769

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rameson, L. T., Morelli, S. A., and Lieberman, M. D. (2012). The neural correlates of empathy: experience, automaticity, and prosocial behavior. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 24, 235–245. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_00130

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Redies, C. (2015). Combining universal beauty and cultural context in a unifying model of visual aesthetic experience. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9:218. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00218

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Riegl, A. (1902). Das holländische Gruppenporträt. Jahrbuch der Allerhöchsten Kaiser Hauses Jahrbuch des allerhöchsten Kaiserhauses 22, 71–278.

Rigato, S., and Farroni, T. (2013). The role of gaze in the processing of emotional facial expressions. Emotion Rev. 5, 36–40. doi: 10.1177/1754073912457225

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Righart, R., and De Gelder, B. (2008). Recognition of facial expressions is influenced by emotional scene gist. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 8, 264–272. doi: 10.3758/CABN.8.3.264

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ringbom, S. (1984). Icon to Narrative: the Rise of the Dramatic Close-Up in Fifteenth-Century Devotional Painting. Doornspijk: DAVACO Publishers.

Russell, J. A. (2003). Core affect and the psychological construction of emotion. Psychol. Rev. 110, 145–172. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.145

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlaffke, L., Lissek, S., Lenz, M., Juckel, G., Schultz, T., Tegenthoff, M., et al. (2015). Shared and non-shared neural networks of cognitive and affective theory-of-mind: a neuroimaging study using cartoon picture stories. Hum. Brain Mapp. 36, 29–39. doi: 10.1002/hbm.22610

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schott, G. D. (2015). Pictures of pain: their contribution to the neuroscience of empathy. Brain 138, 812–820. doi: 10.1093/brain/awu395

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sebastian, C., Fontaine, N., Bird, G., Blakemore, S., Brito, S., McCrory, E., et al. (2012). Neural processing associated with cognitive and affective theory of mind in adolescents and adults. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 7, 53–63. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsr023

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shamay-Tsoory, S. G., Aharon-Peretz, J., and Perry, D. (2009). Two systems for empathy: a double dissociation between emotional and cognitive empathy in inferior frontal gyrus versus ventromedial prefrontal lesions. Brain 132, 617–627. doi: 10.1093/brain/awn279

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sidlauskas, S. (2009). Cézanne's Other: The Portraits of Hortense. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Silveira, S., Fehse, K., Vedder, A., Elvers, K., and Hennig-Fast, K. (2015) Is it the picture or is it the frame? An fMRI study on the neurobiology of framing effects. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9:528. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00528

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Singer, T., and Klimecki, O. M. (2014). Empathy and Compassion. Curr. Biol. 24, 875–878. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2014.06.054

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Slater, M., Antley, A., Davison, A., Swapp, D., Guger, C., Barker, C., et al. (2006). A virtual reprise of the Stanley Milgram obedience experiments. PLoS ONE 1:e39. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0000039

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, L., Bousquet, S., Chang, G., and Smith, J. (2006). Effects of time and information on perception of art. Empirical Studies of the Arts 24, 229–242. doi: 10.2190/DJM0-QBDW-03V7-BLRM

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spaulding, S. (2013). Mirror neurons and social cognition. Mind Lang. 28, 233–257. doi: 10.1111/mila.12017

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spunt, R. P., and Lieberman, M. D. (2012). An integrative model of the neural systems supporting the comprehension of observed emotional behavior. NeuroImage 59, 3050–3059. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.10.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stanley, D., and Adolphs, R. (2013). Toward a neural basis for social behavior. Neuron 80, 816–826. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2013.10.038

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Steinberg, L. (1988). The Philosophical Brothel. October 44, 7–74. doi: 10.2307/778974

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Štech V. V. (1966). Rembrandt. Praha: Odeon.

Steinberg, L. (2001). Leonardo's Incessant Last Supper. New York, NY: Zone Books.

Google Scholar

Stevenson, J. (2010). Performance, Cognitive Theory, and Devotional Culture: Sensual Piety in Late Medieval York, Cognitive Studies in Literature and Performance Series. New York, NY: Palgrave.

Google Scholar

Stoichita, V. (2008). The Pygmalion Effect: From Ovid to Hitchcock. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Swami, V. (2013). Context matters: investigating the impact of contextual information on aesthetic appreciation of paintings by Max Ernst and Pablo Picasso. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 7, 285–295. doi: 10.1037/a0030965

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tamir, D. I., Bricker, A. B., Dodell-Feder, D., and Mitchell, J. P. (2016). Reading fiction and reading minds: the role of simulation in the default network. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 11, 215–224. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsv114

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vemuri, K., and Surampudi, B. (2015). Evidence of stimulus correlated empathy modes – Group ICA of fMRI data. Brain Cogn. 94, 32–43. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2014.12.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vischer, R. (1873). “On the optical sense of form: a contribution to aesthetics,” in Empathy, Form, and Space, eds H. F. Mallgrave and E. Ikonomou (Santa Monica, CA: The Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities), 89–123.

Walter, H. (2012). Social cognitive neuroscience of empathy: concepts, circuits, and genes. Emotion Rev. 4, 9–17. doi: 10.1177/1754073911421379

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as Make-Believe. On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Wangelin, B. C., Bradley, M. M., Kastner, A., and Lang, P. J. (2012). Affective engagement for facial expressions and emotional scenes: the influence of social anxiety. Biol. Psychol. 91, 103–110. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2012.05.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watt, D. F. (2005). Social bonds and the nature of empathy. J. Conscious. Stud. 12, 185–209.

Google Scholar

Wieser, M. J., and Brosch, T. (2012). Faces in context: a review and systematization of contextual influences on affective face processing. Front. Psychol. 3:471. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00471

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wu, L., Winkler, M. H., Andreatta, M., Hajcak, G., and Pauli, P. (2012). Appraisal frames of pleasant and unpleasant pictures alter emotional responses as reflected in self-report and facial electromyographic activity. Int. J. Psychophysiol. 85, 224–229. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2012.04.010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zaki, J. (2013). Cue integration: a common framework for social cognition and physical perception. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 8, 296–312. doi: 10.1177/1745691613475454

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zaki, J., and Ochsner, K. N. (2012). The neuroscience of empathy: progress, pitfalls and promise. Nat. Neurosci. 15, 675–680. doi: 10.1038/nn.3085

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zanon, M., Novembre, G., Zangrando, N., Chittaro, L., and Silani, G. (2014). Brain activity and prosocial behaviour in a simulated life-threatening situation. Neuroimage 98, 134–146. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.04.053

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zillmann, D. (1991). “Empathy: affect from bearing witness to the emotions of others,” in Responding to the Screen: Reception and Reaction Processes, eds J. Bryant and D. Zillmann (Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates), 135–167.

Google Scholar

Zillmann, D. (1994). Mechanisms of emotional involvement with drama, Poetics 23, 33–51.

Google Scholar

Keywords: empathy, art experience, socio-affective processing, affective affordance, esthetic processing, art work

Citation: Kesner L and Horáček J (2017) Empathy-Related Responses to Depicted People in Art Works. Front. Psychol. 8:228. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00228

Received: 28 July 2016; Accepted: 06 February 2017;
Published: 24 February 2017.

Edited by:

Sascha Benjamin Fink, Otto von Guericke University, Magdeburg, Germany

Reviewed by:

Francesco Marchi, Ruhr University Bochum, Germany
Filippo Contesi, Institut Jean Nicod, France

Copyright © 2017 Kesner and Horáček. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Ladislav Kesner, Ladislav.Kesner@nudz.cz

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.