Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 13 December 2017
Sec. Auditory Cognitive Neuroscience
This article is part of the Research Topic Music and the Functions of the Brain: Arousal, Emotions, and Pleasure View all 12 articles

A Neurodynamic Perspective on Musical Enjoyment: The Role of Emotional Granularity

\r\nNathaniel F. Barrett*Nathaniel F. Barrett1*Jay SchulkinJay Schulkin2
  • 1Institute for Culture and Society, University of Navarra, Pamplona, Spain
  • 2Department of Neuroscience, Georgetown University, Washington, DC, United States

Introduction

Musical enjoyment is a nearly universal experience, and yet from a neurocognitive and evolutionary standpoint it presents a conundrum. Why do we respond so powerfully to something apparently without any survival value? A variety of explanations for the evolution of music cognition have been offered (e.g., Wallin et al., 2000; Morley, 2013), nevertheless most current neurocognitive theories of its specifically affective aspects do not posit any specially adapted emotional circuitry (but see Peretz, 2006). Rather, it is assumed that whatever processes are responsible for pleasure and emotion in general—be they subcortical, cortical, or both—are also responsible for the thrills of music. Accordingly, the problem of musical enjoyment is to explain how and why these processes are engaged so effectively by musical stimuli.

While this is a perfectly sensible approach, a major obstacle lies in its path: the paradox of enjoyable sadness in music (Davies, 1994; Levinson, 1997; Garrido and Schubert, 2011; Huron, 2011; Vuoskoski et al., 2011; Kawakami et al., 2013; Taruffi and Koelsch, 2014; Sachs et al., 2015). Music frequently elicits experiences of negative emotions, especially sadness, which we nevertheless find deeply gratifying. For neurocognitive perspectives, the implication of this phenomenon is that normal processes for generating emotional responses are not sufficient to explain musical enjoyment, as something special to music must allow us to enjoy negative emotion. How is musically induced sadness different from “normal” sadness such that the former can be enjoyed while the latter cannot?

To make progress on such questions, in this article we propose a theory of musical enjoyment based on implications of a neurodynamic approach to emotion (Pessoa, 2008; Flaig and Large, 2014), which highlights the role of transient patterns of coordinated neural activity spanning multiple regions of the brain. The key advantage of this perspective is its ability to register the possibility that emotional experiences differ not only in kind (happy vs. sad) but also in “granularity,” complexity, or differentiation (Lindquist and Barrett, 2008). Studies indicate that increased emotional granularity functions as a kind of positivity that can meliorate experiences of negative emotions (Smidt and Sudak, 2015). Accordingly, perhaps we can account for enjoyment of negative emotions in music if we can show that these emotions are more finely differentiated than “normal” negative feelings.

Based on this approach, we also propose a general distinction between pleasure, defined here as bursts of positively categorized feeling, and enjoyment, defined as sustained flows of finely differentiated feeling regardless of emotional categorization (cf. Frederickson, 2002). For this perspective, the categorical meaning of an emotional experience (e.g., happy or sad) is closely related to but separable from its positive or negative affective tone, at least insofar as this tone is influenced by granularity.

Neurodynamics, Emotion, and Music

Here “neurodynamic approach” refers to a family of neurocognitive theories that regard transient, large-scale patterns of rhythmically coordinated neural activity as the main vehicles of cognition/emotion (e.g., Freeman, 1997; Bressler and Kelso, 2001, 2016; Varela et al., 2001; Cosmelli et al., 2007; Breakspear and McIntosh, 2011; Sporns, 2011). An especially pertinent feature of this approach is its divergence from traditional notions of functional specialization and localization (Pessoa, 2008, 2014). Broadly speaking, insofar as neurodynamic theories understand cognitive functions as supported by transient, task-specific coalitions rather than stable processing pathways, they tend to affirm the multifunctionality of neural structures at multiple scales (Anderson et al., 2013; see also Hagoort, 2014; Friederici and Singer, 2015). According to this view, which contrasts with the modular approach commonly adopted by computational theories of neural function, the precise functional role of any given neural structure changes according to the context of coordinated neural activity (McIntosh, 2000, 2004; Bressler and McIntosh, 2007). On the other hand, this approach does not herald a return of “equipotentiality,” as it allows for characterizations of the functional “dispositions” of neural structures (Anderson, 2014).

Similarly, with regard to affect and emotion, the neurodynamic perspective can register the importance of distinct structures—e.g., subcortical structures and hedonic “hotspots” (Berridge and Kringelbach, 2015). But it holds that the full range of emotional experience must be understood in terms of continually evolving patterns of globally coordinated neural activity. Thus, while localized structures may have consistent roles in the production of emotional responses, they do not by themselves constitute emotion nor can they be said to govern emotion in any simple way (Flaig and Large, 2014). The point is not just that emotion is the product of the continual interplay of cortical and subcortical dynamics (Panksepp, 2012). Rather the key implication of neurodynamics is that this interplay is constituted by transient patterns of coordinated activity whose dynamic features—especially complexity and continuity—are relevant to the categorization of emotion and affect (cf. Spivey, 2007 on dynamical categorization). Here, we are mainly interested in the possibility that neurodynamic categorizations of emotional content can range in complexity, corresponding to differences of emotional granularity in experience (analogous to the difference between simple and rich color palettes).

It should be noted that this approach encompasses both categorical theories of “basic emotions” (e.g., Panksepp, 1998, 2007) and dimensional theories of “core affect” (Russell, 2003; Barrett et al., 2007). What is essential for present purposes is the way in which the dynamic interplay between subcortical responses and the complex cortical elaboration of emotion (Reybrouck and Eerola, 2017) gives rise to both categorical distinctions (happy vs. sad) and differences of granularity (fine vs. coarse).

Neurodynamic approaches are well-established in the field of music cognition (for reviews see Large, 2010; Flaig and Large, 2014). Among the advantages of a neurodynamic approach is its capacity to register the relationship between bodily movement and music (e.g., Large et al., 2015). This relationship has been indicated by numerous studies of sensorimotor involvement in music perception (e.g., Chen et al., 2008) and must be taken into account by any theory of musical experience, as we briefly indicate below.

However, few attempts have been made to understand musical enjoyment from a neurodynamic perspective (see Chapin et al., 2010; Flaig and Large, 2014). A notable exception is William Benzon's groundbreaking treatise (Benzon, 2001), which anticipates the perspective offered here. One reason for this neglect is the challenge of empirical verification: like neurodynamic theories of consciousness (Seth et al., 2006), neurodynamic theories of musical experience are in need of high temporal-resolution data (e.g., from EEG or MEG) that show how relevant characteristics of neural dynamics change during musical experience (see Garrett et al., 2013). For the current proposal, the key challenge is to find and measure just those variations that correspond to differences of emotional granularity or complexity. Until such methods are developed, studies of emotional differentiation in musical experience must turn to the refinement of self-reporting methods (Juslin and Sloboda, 2010).

The Paradox of Enjoyable Sadness in Music

In this section, we consider the challenge posed by deeply gratifying experiences of musically induced sadness (Sachs et al., 2015). Sadness is being used here as representative case, as it seems that other negative emotions—despair, terror, dread—can also be induced and enjoyed through music (Gabrielsson, 2011). Also, we do not mean to claim that music is the only source of enjoyable sadness. Rather, our purpose is to use the case of enjoyable sadness in music to set up a distinction between pleasure, defined as bursts of positively categorized feeling, and enjoyment, defined as any sustained flow of high-dimensional feeling, regardless of emotional categorization.

First, let us briefly consider other ways of handling the paradox of enjoyable sadness in music. Some have suggested that music can induce both negative and positive affect at once (Larsen and Stastny, 2011). Others have theorized that sadness might be perceived in music but is not actually felt (Kivy, 1990; Garrido and Schubert, 2011; Kawakami et al., 2013). A third possibility is that sadness is not enjoyed but is compensated for by other positive emotions or by the positive value of the overall experience (Davies, 1994; Huron, 2011). How to decide among these theories?

Part of the problem is that the phenomenological questions raised by enjoyable sadness are subtle and difficult to settle conclusively. Data from self-reporting shows a variety of responses to sad music, including complex emotions that are difficult to put into words (Taruffi and Koelsch, 2014) as well as instances in which sadness is perceived but not felt. Nevertheless, there is ample evidence that music is capable of inducing powerful emotions (Gabrielsson, 2011), including sadness (Vuoskoski and Eerola, 2012), and there is little evidence in support of the idea that musically induced emotions are “less real” than normal emotions (Scherer, 2004). From a physiological standpoint they seem to be identical, evoking the same autonomic responses—chills, elevated heart rate, etc. (Hodges, 2010).

Indeed, musically induced emotions can sometimes feel more real insofar as they are more precisely specified than normal emotions. Felix Mendelssohn famously observed that our experience of emotion in music is “too precise for words,” suggesting that music is used not only to induce but also to expand and enrich emotion (Krueger, 2014). In light of this possibility, we believe that the simplest explanation for the popularity of sad music (e.g., Adele's “Someone Like You”) is that people are drawn to the enjoyment of musically enriched negative emotion for its own sake.

While far from exhaustive, we hope this discussion suffices to indicate that the paradox of enjoyable sadness in music is not yet resolved. The emotion of sadness in musical experience can be vividly real in both physiological and subjective senses and yet also thrilling in a way that normal sadness is not. Moreover, the question of enjoyable sadness is only partly explained by musical features that commonly evoke sadness (Guhn et al., 2007) or by evidence that strong experiences of musical emotion are accompanied by the release of dopamine (Salimpoor et al., 2011), as neither explains how an experience can feel sad and enjoyable at once.

Pleasure and Enjoyment

Philosophers and psychologists have long distinguished between sensory pleasures and more fulfilling experiences of enjoyment and happiness (see Berridge and Kringelbach, 2011; Katz, 2016). For example, a distinction between pleasure and enjoyment is widely affirmed in positive psychology (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990; Frederickson, 2002). However, to our knowledge this distinction has not been verified experimentally.

We believe that a neurodynamic approach can help to refine this distinction and to develop testable hypotheses concerning its neural basis. For instance, based on the neurodynamic approach sketched above, it can be theorized that pleasure pertains to positively categorized feelings that are constituted by the momentary, stereotypical effects of subcortical responses on cortical dynamics. Meanwhile enjoyment might be associated with temporally extended patterns of cortical dynamics that are marked by sustained high dimensionality and that can vary independently of subcortical input. This hypothesis is consistent with studies that suggest that rich sensorimotor engagement can give rise to enjoyment without stimulating any of the drives or appetites normally associated with pleasure (Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2002), but it requires more elaboration in both phenomenological and neurological terms. In short, what is needed is a detailed analysis of interrelated but distinct aspects of positive affect that are frequently lumped together as “positive emotion” (Gruber and Moskowitz, 2014), as granularity seems to be an affective component that is separable from categorical meaning.

Even if we grant this distinction between enjoyment and pleasure, it remains to be demonstrated that emotional granularity can explain enjoyable sadness. The plausibility of our theory is suggested, however, by evidence that finely differentiated negative emotions are experienced as less “unpleasant” (Barrett et al., 2001; Kashdan et al., 2015; Smidt and Sudak, 2015). Although this evidence pertains only to verbal discriminations of emotions, it supports our suggestion that differentiation alters the experience of negative emotion. If Mendelssohn was right about the “preciseness” of musical emotion, then perhaps music can render negative emotions not just endurable but enjoyable. This possibility is supported by evidence that elicitation of a “multifaceted emotional experience” is correlated with the enjoyment of sad music (Taruffi and Koelsch, 2014).

Pleasure and Enjoyment in Music

According to our theory it should be possible to discriminate musical pleasure from enjoyment, although the two are typically mixed together. There are a number of ways for music to give pleasure in the narrow sense; in fact much of what is studied under the rubric of musically induced emotion fits into this category: soothing textures and harmonies, rhythmic coherence and “groove,” and expressive contours or gestures (e.g., Juslin and Vastfjall, 2008). There are also diverse means for the production of musical displeasure—dissonance, noise, rhythmic incoherence, etc. However, because the reception of musical feelings depends on how they are embedded within the overall musical experience, reports of isolated feelings of musical displeasure may be rare. For instance, dissonance is often ingredient in enjoyable music and where it is reported as unpleasant it is usually part of a thoroughly unenjoyable experience of “bad” music (Gabrielsson, 2011).

Musical enjoyment as defined here has been theorized elsewhere (Benzon, 2001) but awaits the formulation of a more precise and testable model of its underlying dynamics. We suggest that resources for constructing such a model are emerging from studies of the musical entrainment—i.e., rhythmic synchronization—of sensorimotor dynamics (e.g., Clayton et al., 2005; Janata et al., 2012; Merchant et al., 2015) and the relationship between music perception and movement (e.g., Maes et al., 2014). Especially pertinent are arguments from ecological psychology that the phenomenon of musical motion—the experience that someone or something is moving in music—is not a metaphorical mapping but rather a direct perceptual experience of various kinds of “virtual motion” (gestures, movement within an environment, etc.) specified by dynamic features of the music itself (Clarke, 2001, 2005; Bharucha et al., 2006; Eitan and Granot, 2006). Together, these viewpoints suggest that musical stimuli can be coupled with sensorimotor processes of the brain in a manner that (1) drives widespread rhythmic coordination of neural activity and (2) overlaps with perceptual experiences of motion in a highly structured environment.

For the present thesis, the key implication is that feelings of negative emotion, when induced by music, are embedded within richly structured experiences of motion which serve to “perceptualize” the experience of emotion. Thus, for instance, a sigh-like phrasing is not just an icon of emotion but also a directly perceived manifestation of emotion. Such manifestations can be categorized in multiple ways—to say that emotions are “perceptualized” does not mean that they are simply “read off” the music. But however they are categorized, musical emotions are experienced through movement and are therefore more concretely formed than “normal” emotion. Musical motion, therefore, is what gives musical emotion its high granularity. What makes negative emotions in music enjoyable is the special way in which music moves us in a quite literal way, as indicated by the close relationship between music and dance (Schulkin, 2013; Fitch, 2016).

In short, what distinguishes the neurodynamic approach is its promise to explain how emotions are co-constituted and enriched by the perceptual experience of music (Krueger, 2014), whereas other approaches usually aim only to explain how emotions are triggered by music. But emotions are not just triggered by music; they are vividly rendered in animate and highly “granular” form by the rhythmic entrainment of experience.

Prospects for Further Research

The central claim of our proposal is that musical enjoyment of negative emotion is distinguished by high emotional granularity in comparison with “normal” (i.e., unenjoyable) experiences of negative emotion. We see two possible ways to test this claim.

One way is to refine methods of self-reporting (Juslin and Sloboda, 2010) in an attempt to gather data about the emotional granularity of musical experiences. It should be emphasized that most published studies of emotional granularity have aimed only to measure subjects' verbal capacity to discriminate emotions (Smidt and Sudak, 2015); this capacity is, at best, an indirect measure of the actual emotional granularity of experience (see Lindquist and Barrett, 2008). Here, we are interested only in experienced emotional granularity; moreover we are interested in how this granularity varies in response to music. Self-reporting is notoriously unreliable, and continuous variations of granularity are likely to be even harder to report than categorical distinctions (e.g., happy/sad). Nevertheless, while acknowledging these limitations, we believe that self-reporting methods could be used to test our theory—as suggested by at least one study (Taruffi and Koelsch, 2014).

A second possible test would be to measure variations of emotional granularity using high temporal-resolution techniques such as EEG and MEG. In recent years, neuroscientists who adopt a neurodynamic approach have begun using these techniques to measure “moment-to-moment brain signal variability” associated with cognitive functioning (Heisz et al., 2012; Garrett et al., 2013; Miskovic et al., 2016) and at least one study has attempted to measure correlations between individual emotional granularity and brain activity during “affective processing” (Lee et al., 2017). To test our proposal what is needed is a way to test variations of granularity within the same individual in response to music, and for this it is necessary to develop a measure of emotional complexity (cf. Seth et al., 2006). If such a measure could be developed, our expectation is that experiences of musically induced negative emotion would be found to correlate with higher levels of complexity than “normally” induced (e.g., IAPS-induced) negative emotion.

At present, however, there is no evidence that directly supports our theory. Even so, we believe that the idea of emotional granularity as a factor in musical enjoyment is plausible and worthy of further investigation. Moreover, it should be noted that the thesis presented here is not just about musical enjoyment: it is also about the role of granularity in enjoyment, pleasure, and emotional experience in general. As such, its various phenomenological and neurological implications need to be further articulated and tested against a very wide array of empirical evidence. The key insight of this perspective, which fits well with a neurodynamic approach, is that emotional experiences can vary in dimensionality (coarse vs. fine) as well as categorical meaning (happy vs. sad).

Author Contributions

NB and JS made contributions to the drafting and revision of this work at all stages and share responsibility for its content.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Anderson, M. L. (2014). After Phrenology: Neural Reuse and the Interactive Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Anderson, M. L., Kinnison, J., and Pessoa, L. (2013). Describing functional diversity of brain regions and brain networks. Neuroimage 73, 50–58. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2013.01.071

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F., Gross, J., Christensen, T. C., and Benvenuto, M. (2001). Knowing what you're feeling and knowing what to do about it: mapping the relation between emotion differentiation and emotion regulation. Cogn. Emot. 15, 713–724. doi: 10.1080/02699930143000239

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F., Mesquita, B., Ochsner, K. N., and Gross, J. J. (2007). The experience of emotion. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 58, 373–403. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085709

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Benzon, W. (2001). Beethoven's Anvil: Music in Mind and Culture. New York, NY: Basic Books.

Google Scholar

Berridge, K., and Kringelbach, M. L. (2011). Building a neuroscience of pleasure and well-being. Psychol. Well Being 1:3. doi: 10.1186/2211-1522-1-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berridge, K., and Kringelbach, M. L. (2015). Pleasure systems in the brain. Neuron 86, 646–664. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2015.02.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bharucha, J. J., Curtis, M., and Paroo, K. (2006). Varieties of musical experience. Cognition 100, 131–172. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2005.11.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Breakspear, M., and McIntosh, A. R. (2011). Networks, noise, and models: reconceptualizing the brain as a complex, distributed system. Neuroimage 58, 293–295. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.03.056

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text

Bressler, S. L., and Kelso, J. A. S. (2001). Cortical coordination dynamics and cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. (Regul. Ed). 5, 26–36. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01564-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bressler, S. L., and Kelso, J. A. S. (2016). Coordination dynamics in cognitive neuroscience. Front. Neurosci. 10:397. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2016.00397

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bressler, S. L., and McIntosh, A. R. (2007). “The role of neural context in large-scale neurocognitive network operations,” in Handbook of Brain Connectivity, eds V. K. Jirsa and A. R. McIntosh (Berlin: Springer), 403–419.

Google Scholar

Chapin, H., Jantzen, K. J., Kelso, J. A. S., Steinberg, F., and Large, E. W. (2010). Dynamic emotional and neural responses to music depend on performance expression and listener experience. PLoS ONE 5:e13812. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0013812

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chen, J. L., Penhune, V. B., and Zatorre, R. J. (2008). Listening to musical rhythms recruits motor regions of the brain. Cereb. Cortex 18, 2844–2854. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhn042

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clarke, E. (2001). Meaning and the specification of motion in music. Music. Sci. 5, 213–234. doi: 10.1177/102986490100500205

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clarke, E. (2005). Ways of Listening: An Ecological Approach to the Perception of Musical Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195151947.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clayton, M., Sager, R., and Will, U. (2005). In time with the music: the concept of entrainment and its significance for ethnomusicology. Eur. Meet. Ethnomusicol. 11, 3–75.

Google Scholar

Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-P., and Thompson, E. (2007). “Neurodynamical approaches to consciousness,” in The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness, eds P. D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, and E. Thompson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 731–752.

Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow: The Psychology of Optimal Experience. New York, NY: Harper and Row.

Google Scholar

Davies, S. (1994). Musical Meaning and Expression. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Google Scholar

Eitan, Z., and Granot, R. Y. (2006). How music moves. Music Percept. 23, 221–248. doi: 10.1525/mp.2006.23.3.221

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fitch, W. T. (2016). Dance, music, meter and groove: a forgotten partnership. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 10:64. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00064

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Flaig, N. K., and Large, E. W. (2014). Dynamical musical communication of core affect. Front. Psychol. 5:72. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00072

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frederickson, B. L. (2002). “Positive emotions,” in Handbook of Positive Psychology, eds C. R. Snyder and S. J. Lopez (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 120–134.

Freeman, W. J. (1997). Nonlinear neurodynamics and intentionality. J. Mind Behav. 18, 291–304.

Google Scholar

Friederici, A. D., and Singer, W. (2015). Grounding language processing on basic neurophysiological principles. Trends Cogn. Sci. (Regul. Ed). 19, 329–338. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2015.03.012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gabrielsson, A. (2011). Strong Experiences with Music [Transl. by R. Bradbury]. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199695225.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Garrett, D. D., Samanez-Larkin, G. R., MacDonald, S. W. S., Lindenberger, U., McIntosh, A. R., and Grady, C. L. (2013). Moment-to-moment brain signal variability: a next frontier in human brain mapping? Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 37, 610–624. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2013.02.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Garrido, S., and Schubert, E. (2011). Negative emotion in music: what is the attraction? A qualitative study. Empiric. Musicol. Rev. 6, 214–230. doi: 10.18061/1811/52950

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gruber, J., and Moskowitz, J. T. (eds.). (2014). Positive Emotion: Integrating the Light Sides and Dark Sides. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199926725.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text

Guhn, M., Hamm, A., and Zentner, M. (2007). Physiological and musico-acoustic correlates of the chill response. Music Perception 24, 473–484. doi: 10.1525/mp.2007.24.5.473

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hagoort, P. (2014). Nodes and networks in the neural architecture for language: Broca's region and beyond. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 28, 136–141. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2014.07.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Heisz, J. J., Shedden, J. M., and McIntosh, A. R. (2012). Relating brain signal variability to knowledge representation. Neuroimage 63, 1384–1392. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.08.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hodges, D. A. (2010). “Psychophysiological measures,” in Handbook of Music and Emotion: Theory, Research, Applications, eds P. N. Juslin and J. A. Sloboda (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 279–311.

Google Scholar

Huron, D. (2011). Why is sad music pleasurable? A possible role for prolactin. Music. Sci. 15, 146–158. doi: 10.1177/1029864911401171

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Janata, P., Tomic, S. T., and Haberman, J. M. (2012). Sensorimotor coupling in music and the psychology of the groove. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 141, 54–75. doi: 10.1037/a0024208

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Juslin, P. N., and Sloboda, J. A. (eds.). (2010). Handbook of Music and Emotion: Theory, Research, Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Juslin, P. N., and Västfjäll, D. (2008). Emotional responses to music: the need to consider underlying mechanisms. Behav. Brain Sci. 31, 559–621. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X08005293

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kashdan, T. B., Barrett, L. F., and McKnight, P. E. (2015). Unpacking emotion differentiation: transforming unpleasant experience by perceiving distinctions in negativity. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 24, 10–16. doi: 10.1177/0963721414550708

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Katz, L. D. (2016). “Pleasure,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed E. N. Zalta. Available online at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/pleasure/

Google Scholar

Kawakami, A., Furukawa, K., Katahira, K., and Okanoya, K. (2013). Sad music induces pleasant emotion. Front. Psychol. 4:311. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00311

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kivy, P. (1990). Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections on the Purely Musical Experience. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Google Scholar

Krueger, J. (2014). Affordances and the musically extended mind. Front. Psychol. 4:1003. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Large, E. W. (2010). “Neurodynamics of music,” in Music Perception, ed M. Reiss Jones, R. R. Fay, and A. N. Popper (New York, NY: Springer), 201–231. doi: 10.1007/978-1-4419-6114-3_7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Large, E. W., Herrera, J. A., and Velasco, M. J. (2015). Neural networks for beat perception in musical rhythm. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 9:159. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2015.00159

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Larsen, J. T., and Stastny, B. J. (2011). It's a bittersweet symphony: simultaneously mixed emotional responses to music with conflicting cues. Emotion 11, 1469–1473. doi: 10.1037/a0024081

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lee, J. Y., Lindquist, K. A., and Nam, C. S. (2017). Emotional granularity effects on event-related brain potentials during affective picture processing. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 11:133. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00133

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Levinson, J. (1997). “Music and negative emotion,” in Music and Meaning, ed. J. Robinson (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press), 215–241.

Google Scholar

Lindquist, K. A., and Barrett, L. F. (2008). “Emotional complexity,” in Handbook of Emotions, 3rd Edn., eds M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, and L. F. Barrett (New York, NY: Guilford Press), 513–530.

Google Scholar

Maes, P.-J., Leman, M., Palmer, C., and Wanderley, M. M. (2014). Action-based effects on music perception. Front. Psychol. 4:1008. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McIntosh, A. R. (2000). Towards a network theory of cognition. Neural Networks 13, 861–870. doi: 10.1016/S0893-6080(00)00059-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McIntosh, A. R. (2004). Contexts and catalysts: a resolution of the localization and integration of function in the brain. Neuroinformatics 4, 175–182. doi: 10.1385/NI:2:2:175

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Merchant, H., Grahn, J., Trainor, L., Rohrmeier, M., and Fitch, W. T. (2015). Finding the beat: a neural perspective across humans and non-human primates. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B 370:20140093. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2014.0093

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Miskovic, V., Owens, M., Kuntzelman, K., and Gibb, B. E. (2016). Charting moment-to-moment brain signal variability from early to late childhood. Cortex 83, 51–61. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2016.07.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Morley, I. (2013). The Prehistory of Music: Human Evolution, Archaeology and the Origins of Musicality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199234080.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nakamura, J., and Csikszentmihalyi, M. (2002). “The concept of flow,” in Handbook of Positive Psychology, eds C. R. Snyder and S. J. Lopez (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 89–105.

Google Scholar

Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Panksepp, J. (2007). Neurologizing the psychology of affects: how appraisal-based constructivism and basic emotion theory can coexist. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2, 281–296. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2007.00045.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Panksepp, J. (2012). What is an emotional feeling? Lessons about affective origins from cross-species neuroscience. Motiv. Emot. 36, 4–15. doi: 10.1007/s11031-011-9232-y

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Peretz, I. (2006). The nature of music from a biological perspective. Cognition 100, 1–32. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2005.11.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pessoa, L. (2008). On the relationship between emotion and cognition. Nat. Neurosci. Rev. 9, 148–158. doi: 10.1038/nrn2317

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pessoa, L. (2014). Understanding brain networks and brain organization. Phys. Life Rev. 11, 400–435. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2014.03.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Reybrouck, M., and Eerola, T. (2017). Music and its inductive power: a psychobiological and evolutionary approach to musical emotions. Front. Psychol. 8:494. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00494

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Russell, J. A. (2003). Core affect and the psychological construction of emotion. Psychol. Rev. 100, 145–172. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.145

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sachs, M. E., Damasio, A., and Habibi, A. (2015). The pleasures of sad music: a systematic review. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9:404. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00404

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Salimpoor, V. N., Benovoy, M., Larcher, K., Dagher, A., and Zatorre, R. J. (2011). Anatomically distinct dopamine release during anticipation and experience of peak emotion to music. Nat. Neurosci. 14, 257–264. doi: 10.1038/nn.2726

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scherer, K. R. (2004). Which emotions can be induced by music? What are the underlying mechanisms? And how can we measure them? J. New Music Res. 33, 239–251. doi: 10.1080/0929821042000317822

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schulkin, J. (2013). Reflections on the Musical Mind: An Evolutionary Perspective. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. doi: 10.1515/9781400849031

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seth, A. K., Izhikevich, E., Reeke, G. N., and Edelman, G. M. (2006). Theories and measures of consciousness: an extended framework. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 10799–10804. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0604347103

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smidt, K. E., and Sudak, M. K. (2015). A brief, but nuanced, review of emotional granularity and emotion differentiation research. Curr. Opin. Psychol. 3, 48–51. doi: 10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.02.007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spivey, M. J. (2007). The Continuity of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Taruffi, L., and Koelsch, S. (2014). The paradox of music-evoked sadness: an online survey. PLoS ONE 9:e110490. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0110490

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varela, F., Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., and Martinerie, J. (2001). The brainweb: phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nat. Neurosci. Rev. 2, 229–239. doi: 10.1038/35067550

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vuoskoski, J. K., and Eerola, T. (2012). Can sad music really make you sad? Indirect measures of affective states induced by music and autobiographical memories. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 6, 204–213. doi: 10.1037/a0026937

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vuoskoski, J. K., Thompson, W. F., McIlwain, D., and Eerola, T. (2011). Who enjoys listening to sad music and why? Music Percept. 29, 311–318. doi: 10.1525/mp.2012.29.3.311

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wallin, N. L., Merker, B., and Brown, S. (eds.). (2000). The Origins of Music. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Keywords: music cognition, music and emotion, granularity of emotion, neurodynamical models, musical enjoyment

Citation: Barrett NF and Schulkin J (2017) A Neurodynamic Perspective on Musical Enjoyment: The Role of Emotional Granularity. Front. Psychol. 8:2187. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.02187

Received: 19 October 2016; Accepted: 30 November 2017;
Published: 13 December 2017.

Edited by:

Tuomas Eerola, Durham University, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Mireille Besson, Institut de Neurosciences Cognitives de la Méditerranée (INCM), France
Mark Reybrouck, KU Leuven, Belgium
Andrea Schiavio, University of Graz, Austria

Copyright © 2017 Barrett and Schulkin. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Nathaniel F. Barrett, nbarrett@unav.es

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.